1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
|
\documentclass[../lic_malinka.tex]{subfiles}
\begin{document}
In this section we will take a closer look at classes of finitely
generated structures with some characteristic properties. More
specifically, we will describe a concept developed by a French
mathematician Roland Fraïssé called Fraïssé limit.
\subsection{Definitions}
\begin{definition}
Let $L$ be a signature and $M$ be an $L$-structure. The \emph{age} of $M$ is
the class $\bK$ of all finitely generated structures that embed into $M$.
The age of $M$ is also associated with class of all structures embeddable in
$M$ \emph{up to isomorphism}.
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
We say that $M$ has \emph{countable age} when its age has countably many
isomorphism types of finitely generated structures.
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated structures. $\bK$ has
\emph{hereditary property (HP)} if for any $A\in\bK$, any finitely generated
substructure $B$ of $A$ it holds that $B\in\bK$.
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated structures. We say that $\bK$ has
\emph{joint embedding property (JEP)} if for any $A, B\in\bK$ there is a
structure $C\in\bK$ such that both $A$ and $B$ embed in $C$.
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
& C & \\
A \arrow[ur, dashed, "f"] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed, "g"']
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
In terms of category theory, this is a \emph{span} in category $\bK$.
\end{definition}
Fraïssé has shown fundamental theories regarding age of a structure, one of
them being the following one:
\begin{fact}
\label{fact:age_is_hpjep}
Suppose $L$ is a signature and $\bK$ is a nonempty finite or countable set
of finitely generated $L$-structures. Then $\bK$ has the HP and JEP if
and only if $\bK$ is the age of some finite or countable structure.
\end{fact}
Beside the HP and JEP Fraïssé has distinguished one more property of the
class $\bK$, namely amalgamation property.
\begin{definition}
Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated $L$-structures. We say that $\bK$
has the \emph{amalgamation property (AP)} if for any $A, B, C\in\bK$ and
embeddings $e\colon C\to A, f\colon C\to B$ there exists $D\in\bK$ together
with embeddings $g\colon A\to D$ and $h\colon A\to D$ such that
$g\circ e = h\circ f$.
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
& D & \\
A \arrow[ur, dashed, "g"] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed, "h"'] \\
& C \arrow[ur, "f"'] \arrow[ul, "e"] &
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
\end{definition}
In terms of category theory, amalgamation over some structure $C$ is a
pushout diagram.
\begin{definition}
Let $M$ be an $L$-structure. $M$ is \emph{ultrahomogeneous} if every
isomorphism between finitely generated substructures of $M$ extends to an
automorphism of $M$.
\end{definition}
Having those definitions we can provide the main Fraïssé theorem.
\begin{theorem}[Fraïssé theorem]
\label{theorem:fraisse_thm}
Let L be a countable language and let $\bK$ be a nonempty countable set of
finitely generated $L$-structures which has HP, JEP and AP. Then $\bK$ is
the age of a countable, ultrahomogeneous $L$-structure $M$. Moreover, $M$ is
unique up to isomorphism. We say that $M$ is a \emph{Fraïssé limit} of $\bK$
and denote this by $M = \Flim(\bK)$.
\end{theorem}
This is a well known theorem. One can read a proof of this theorem in Wilfrid
Hodges' classical book \textit{Model Theory}~\cite{hodges_1993}. In the proof
of this theorem appears another, equally important \ref{lemma:weak_ultrahom}.
\begin{definition}
We say that an $L$-structure $M$ is \emph{weakly ultrahomogeneous} if for any
$A, B$ finitely generated substructures of $M$ such that $A\subseteq B$ and
an embedding $f\colon A\to M$ there is an embedding $g\colon B\to M$ which
extends $f$.
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
A \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "f"] & D \\
B \arrow[ur, dashed, "g"']
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
\end{definition}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma:weak_ultrahom}
A countable structure is ultrahomogeneous if and only if it is weakly
ultrahomogeneous.
\end{lemma}
This lemma will play a major role in the later parts of the paper. Weak
ultrahomogeneity is an easier and more intuitive property and it will prove
useful when recursively constructing the generic automorphism of a Fraïssé
limit.
% \begin{fact} If $\bK$ is a uniformly locally finite Fraïssé class, then
% $\Flim(\bK)$ is $\aleph_0$-categorical and has quantifier elimination.
% \end{fact}
\subsection{Random graph}
In this section we'll take a closer look on a class of finite unordered graphs,
which is a Fraïssé class.
The language of unordered graphs $L$ consists of a single binary
relational symbol $E$. If $G$ is an $L$-structure then we call it a
\emph{graph}, and its elements $\emph{vertices}$. If for some vertices
$u, v\in G$ we have $G\models uEv$ then we say that there is an $\emph{edge}$
connecting $u$ and $v$. If $G\models \forall x\forall y (xEy\leftrightarrow yEx)$
then we say that $G$ is an \emph{unordered graph}. From now on we omit the word
\textit{unordered} and graphs as unordered.
\begin{proposition}
Let $\cG$ be the class of all finite graphs. $\cG$ is a Fraïssé class.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
$\cG$ is of course countable (up to isomorphism) and has the HP
(graph substructure is also a graph). It has JEP: having two finite graphs
$G_1,G_2$ take their disjoint union $G_1\sqcup G_2$ as the extension of them
both. $\cG$ has the AP. Having graphs $A, B, C$, where $B$ and $C$ are
supergraphs of $A$, we can assume without loss of generality, that
$(B\setminus A) \cap (C\setminus A) = \emptyset$. Then
$A\sqcup (B\setminus A)\sqcup (C\setminus A)$ is the graph we're looking
for (with edges as in B and C and without any edges between $B\setminus A$
and $C\setminus A$).
\end{proof}
\begin{definition}
\label{definition:random_graph}
The \emph{random graph} is the Fraïssé limit of the class of finite graphs
$\cG$ denoted by $\FrGr = \Flim(\cG)$.
\end{definition}
The concept of the random graph emerges independently in many fields of
mathematics. For example, one can construct the graph by choosing at random
for each pair of vertices if they should be connected or not. It turns out
that the graph constructed this way is isomorphic to the random graph with
probability 1.
The random graph $\FrGr$ has one particular property that is unique to the
random graph.
\begin{fact}[random graph property]
For each finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq \FrGr$ there exists $v\in\FrGr\setminus (X\cup Y)$
such that $\forall u\in X (vEu)$ and $\forall u\in Y (\neg vEu)$.
\end{fact}
\begin{proof}
Take any finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq\FrGr$. Let $G_{XY}$ be the
subgraph of $\FrGr$ induced by the $X\cup Y$. Let $H = G_{XY}\cup \{w\}$,
where $w$ is a new vertex that does not appear in $G_{XY}$. Also, $w$ is connected to
all vertices of $G_{XY}$ that come from $X$ and to none of those that come
from $Y$. This graph is of course finite, so it is embeddable in $\FrGr$.
Without loss of generality assume that this embedding is simply inclusion.
Let $f$ be the partial isomorphism from $X\sqcup Y$ to $H$, with $X$ and
$Y$ projected to the part of $H$ that come from $X$ and $Y$ respectively.
By the ultrahomogeneity of $\FrGr$ this isomorphism extends to an automorphism
$\sigma\in\Aut(\FrGr)$. Then $v = \sigma^{-1}(w)$ is the vertex we sought.
\end{proof}
\begin{fact}
If a countable graph $G$ has the random graph property, then it is
isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
\end{fact}
\begin{proof}
Enumerate vertices of both graphs: $\FrGr = \{a_1, a_2\ldots\}$ and $G
= \{b_1, b_2\ldots\}$.
We will construct a chain of partial isomorphisms $f_n\colon \FrGr\to G$
such that $\emptyset = f_0\subseteq f_1\subseteq f_2\subseteq\ldots$ and $a_n \in
\dom(f_n)$ and $b_n\in\rng(f_n)$.
Suppose we have $f_n$. We seek $b\in G$ such that $f_n\cup \{\langle
a_{n+1}, b\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism.
If $a_{n+1}\in\dom{f_n}$, then simply $b = f_n(a_{n+1})$. Otherwise,
let $X = \{a\in\FrGr\mid
aE_{\FrGr} a_{n+1}\}\cap \dom{f_n}, Y = X^{c}\cap \dom{f_n}$, i.e. $X$ are
vertices of $\dom{f_n}$ that are connected with $a_{n+1}$ in $\FrGr$ and
$Y$ are those vertices that are not connected with $a_{n+1}$. Let $b$ be
a vertex of $G$ that is connected to all vertices of $f_n[X]$ and to none
$f_n[Y]$ (it exists by the random graph property). Then $f_n\cup \{\langle
a_{n+1}, b\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism. We find $a$ for the
$b_{n+1}$ in the similar manner, so that $f_{n+1} = f_n\cup \{\langle
a_{n+1}, b\rangle, \langle a, b_{n+1}\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism.
Finally, $f = \bigcup^{\infty}_{n=0}f_n$ is an isomorphism between $\FrGr$
and $G$. Take any $a, b\in \FrGr$. Then for some big enough $n$ we have
that $aE_{\FrGr}b\Leftrightarrow f_n(a)E_{G}f_n(b) \Leftrightarrow f(a)E_{G}f(b)$.
\end{proof}
Using this fact one can show that the graph constructed in the probabilistic
manner is in fact isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
\begin{definition} We say that a Fraïssé class $\bK$ has \emph{weak
Hrushovski property} (\emph{WHP}) if for every $A\in \bK$ and an isomorphism
of its substructures $p\colon A\to A$ (also called a partial automorphism of $A$),
there is some $B\in \bK$ such
that $p$ can be extended to an automorphism of $B$, i.e.\ there is an
embedding $i\colon A\to B$ and a $\bar p\in \Aut(B)$ such that the following
diagram commutes:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
B\ar[r,dashed,"\bar p"]&B\\
A\ar[u,dashed,"i"]\ar[r,"p"]&A\ar[u,dashed,"i"]
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
\end{definition}
\begin{proposition}
\label{proposition:finite-graphs-whp}
The class of finite graphs $\cG$ has the weak Hrushovski property.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
It may be there some day, but it may not!
\end{proof}
\subsection{Canonical amalgamation}
\begin{definition}
Let $\bK$ be a class finitely generated $L$-structures. We say that
$\bK$ has \emph{canonical amalgamation} if for every $C\in\bK$ there
is a functor $\otimes_C\colon\Cospan(\bK)\to\Pushout(\bK)$ such that
it has the following properties:
\begin{itemize}
\item Let $A\leftarrow C\rightarrow B$ be a cospan. Then $\otimes_C$ sends
it to a pushout that preserves ``the bottom`` structures and embeddings, i.e.:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
& & & & A\otimes_C B & \\
A & & B \arrow[r, dashed, "A\otimes_C B"] & A \arrow[ur, dashed] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed] \\
& C \arrow[ul] \arrow[ur] & & & C \arrow[ul] \arrow[ur] &
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
We have deliberately omitted names for embeddings of $C$. Of course,
the functor has to take them into account, but this abuse of notation
is convenient and should not lead into confusion.
\item Let $A\leftarrow C\rightarrow B$, $A'\leftarrow C\rightarrow B'$ be cospans
with a natural transformation given by $\alpha\colon A\to A', \beta\colon B\to B',
\gamma\colon C\to C$. Then $\otimes_C$ preserves the morphisms of
when sending the natural transformation of those cospans to natural
transformation of pushouts by adding the
$\delta\colon A\otimes_C B\to A'\otimes_C B'$ morphism:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
& A'\otimes_C B' & \\
A' \arrow[ur] & & B' \arrow[ul] \\
& A\otimes_C B \ar[uu, dashed, "\delta"] & \\
& C \arrow[uul, bend left] \arrow[uur, bend right] & \\
A \arrow[uuu, dashed, "\alpha"] \arrow[uur, bend left, crossing over] & & B \arrow[uuu, dashed, "\beta"'] \arrow[uul, bend right, crossing over] \\
& C \arrow[ur] \arrow[ul] \arrow[uu, dashed, "\gamma"] & \\
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
% \begin{center}
% \begin{tikzcd}
% & A \ar[rrr, dashed, "\alpha"] \ar[drr, bend left=20, crossing over] & & & A' \ar[dr] & \\
% C \ar[rr, dashed, "\gamma"] \ar[ur] \ar[dr] & & C \ar[rrd, bend right=20] \ar[rru, bend left=20] & A\otimes_C B \ar[rr, dashed, "\delta"] & & A' \otimes_C B' \\
% & B \ar[rrr, dashed, "\beta"] \ar[urr, bend right=20, crossing over] & & & B' \ar[ur] & \\
% \end{tikzcd}
% \end{center}
\end{itemize}
\end{definition}
\begin{theorem}
\label{theorem:canonical_amalgamation_thm}
Let $\bK$ be a Fraïssé class of $L$-structures with canonical amalgamation.
Then the class $\cH$ of $L$-structures with automorphism is a Fraïssé class.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
$\cH$ is obviously countable and has HP. It suffices to show that it
has AP (JEP follows by taking $C$ to be the empty structure). Take any
$(A,\alpha), (B,\beta), (C,\gamma)\in \cH$ such that $(C,\gamma)$ embeds
into $(A,\alpha)$ and $(B,\beta)$. Then $\alpha, \beta, \gamma$ yield
an automorphism $\eta$ (as a natural transformation) of a cospan:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
A & & B \\
% & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] & \\
A \ar[u, dashed, "\alpha"] & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] & B \ar[u, dashed, "\beta"'] \\
& C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] \ar[u, dashed, "\gamma"] &
% (A, \alpha) & & (B, \beta) \\
% & (C, \gamma) \ar[ur] \ar[ul] &
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
Then, by the fact \ref{fact:functor_iso}, $\otimes_C(\eta)$ is an automorphism
of the pushout diagram:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
& A\otimes_C B \ar[loop above, "\delta"] & \\
A \ar[ur] \ar[loop left, "\alpha"]& & B \ar[ul] \ar[loop right, "\beta"]\\
& C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] \ar[loop below, "\gamma"] &
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
TODO: ten diagram nie jest do końca taki jak trzeba, trzeba w zasadzie skopiować
ten z definicji kanonicznej amalgamcji. Czy to nie będzie wyglądać źle?
This means that the morphism $\delta\colon A\otimes_C B\to A\otimes_C B$
has to be automorphism. Thus, by the fact that the diagram commutes,
we have the amalgamation of $(A, \alpha)$ and $(B, \beta)$ over $(C,\gamma)$
in $\cH$.
\end{proof}
\subsection{Graphs with automorphism}
The language and theory of unordered graphs is fairly simple. We extend the
language by one unary symbol $\sigma$ and interpret it as an arbitrary
automorphism on the graph structure. It turns out that the class of such
structures is a Fraïssé class.
\begin{proposition}
Let $\cH$ be the class of all finite graphs with an automorphism, i.e.
structures in the language $(E, \sigma)$ such that $E$ is a symmetric
relation and $\sigma$ is an automorphism on the structure. $\cH$ is
a Fraïssé class.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
Countability and HP are obvious, JEP follows by the same argument as in
plain graphs. We need to show that the class has the amalgamation property.
Take any $(A, \alpha), (B, \beta), (C,\gamma)\in\cH$ such that $A$ embeds
into $B$ and $C$. Without the loss of generality we may assume that
$B\cap C = A$ and $\alpha\subseteq\beta,\gamma$.
Let $D$ be the amalgamation of $B$ and $C$ over $A$ as in
the proof for the plain graphs. We will define the automorphism
$\delta\in\Aut(D)$ so it extends $\beta$ and $\gamma$.
We let $\delta\upharpoonright_B = \beta, \delta\upharpoonright_C = \gamma$.
Let's check the definition is correct. We have to show that
$(uE_Dv\leftrightarrow \delta(u)E_D\delta(v))$ holds for any $u, v\in
D$. We have two cases:
\begin{itemize}
\item $u, v\in X$, where $X$ is either $B$ or $C$. This case is trivial.
\item $u\in B\setminus A, v\in C\setminus A$. Then
$\delta(u)=\beta(u)\in B\setminus A$, similarly $\delta(v)=\gamma(v)\in
C\setminus A$. This follows from the fact, that $\beta\upharpoonright_A
= \alpha$, so for any $w\in A\quad\beta^{-1}(w)=\alpha^{-1}(w)\in A$,
similarly for $\gamma$. Thus, from the construction of $D$, $\neg uE_Dv$
and $\neg \delta(u)E_D\delta(v)$.
\end{itemize}
\end{proof}
The proposition says that there is a Fraïssé for the class $\cH$ of finite
graphs with automorphisms. We shall call it $(\FrAut, \sigma)$. Not
surprisingly, $\FrAut$ is in fact a random graph.
\begin{proposition}
\label{proposition:graph-aut-is-normal}
The Fraïssé limit of $\cH$ interpreted as a plain graph (i.e. as a reduct
to the language of graphs) is isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
It is enough to show that $\FrAut = \Flim(\cH)$ has the random graph
property. Take any finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq \FrAut$. Without the loss
of generality assume that $X\cup Y$ is $\sigma$-invariant, i.e.
$\sigma(v)\in X\cup Y$ for $v\in X\cup Y$. This assumption can be made
because there are no infinite orbits in $\sigma$, which in turn is due to
the fact that $\cH$ is the age of $\FrAut$.
Let $G_{XY}$ be the graph induced by $X\cup Y$. Take $H=G_{XY}\sqcup {v}$
as a supergraph of $G_{XY}$ with one new vertex $v$ connected to all
vertices of $X$ and to none of $Y$. By the proposition
\ref{proposition:finite-graphs-whp} we can extend $H$ together with its
partial isomorphism $\sigma\upharpoonright_{X\cup Y}$ to a graph $R$ with
automorphism $\tau$. Once again, without the loss of generality we can
assume that $R\subseteq\FrAut$, because $\cH$ is the age of $\FrAut$. But
$R\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$ together with $\tau\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$
are isomorphic to the $G_{XY}$ with $\sigma\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$.
Thus, by ultrahomogeneity of $\FrAut$ this isomorphism extends to an
automorphism $\theta$ of $(\FrAut, \sigma)$. Then $\theta(v)$ is the vertex
that is connected to all vertices of $X$ and none of $Y$, because
$\theta[R\upharpoonright_X] = X, \theta[R\upharpoonright_Y] = Y$.
\end{proof}
\begin{theorem}
\label{theorem:isomorphic_fr_lims}
Let $\cC$ be a Fraïssé class of finite structures in a relational language
$L$ of some theory $T$. Let $\cD$ be a class of finite structures of the
theory $T$ in a relational language $L$ with additional unary function
symbol interpreted as an automorphism of the structure. If $\cC$ has the
weak Hrushovski property and $\cD$ is a Fraïssé class then the Fraïssé
limit of $\cC$ is isomorphic to the Fraïssé limit of $\cD$ reduced
to the language $L$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
Let $\Gamma=\Flim(\cC)$ and $(\Pi, \sigma) =\Flim(\cD)$. By the Fraïssé
theorem \ref{theorem:fraisse_thm} it suffices to show that the age of $\Pi$
is $\cC$ and that it has the weak ultrahomogeneity in the class $\cC$. The
former comes easily, as for every structure $A\in \cC$ we have the structure
$(A, \id_A)\in \cD$, which means that the structure $A$ embeds into $\Pi$.
Also, if a structure $(B, \beta)\in\cD$ embeds into $\cD$, then $B\in\cC$.
Hence, $\cC$ is indeed the age of $\Pi$.
Now, take any structure $A, B\in\cC$ such that $A\subseteq B$. Without the
loss of generality assume that $A = B\cap \Pi$. Let $\bar{A}$ be the
smallest structure closed on the automorphism $\sigma$ and containing $A$.
It is finite, as $\cC$ is the age of $\Pi$. By the weak Hrushovski property,
of $\cC$ let $(\bar{B}, \beta)$ be a structure extending
$(B\cup \bar{A}, \sigma\upharpoonright_{\bar{A}})$. Again, we may assume
that $B\cup \bar{A}\subseteq \bar{B}$. Then, by the fact that $\Pi$ is a
Fraïssé limit of $\cD$ there is an embedding
$f\colon(\bar{B}, \beta)\to(\Pi, \sigma)$
such that the following diagram commutes:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
(A, \emptyset) \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & (\bar{A}, \sigma\upharpoonright_A) \arrow[d, "\subseteq"] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & (\Pi, \sigma) \\
(B, \sigma\upharpoonright_B) \arrow[r, dashed, "\subseteq"'] & (\bar{B}, \beta) \arrow[ur, dashed, "f"]
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
Then we simply get the following diagram:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
A \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & \Pi \\
B \arrow[ur, dashed, "f\upharpoonright_B"']
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
which proves that $\Pi$ is indeed a weakly ultrahomogeneous structure in $\cC$.
Hence, it is isomorphic to $\Gamma$.
\end{proof}
\end{document}
|