1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
|
\documentclass[../lic_malinka.tex]{subfiles}
\begin{document}
\subsection{Descriptive set theory}
\begin{definition}
Suppose $X$ is a topological space and $A\subseteq X$.
We say that $A$ is \emph{meagre} in $X$ if $A = \bigcup_{n\in\bN}A_n$,
where $A_n$ are nowhere dense subsets of $X$ (i.e. $\Int(\bar{A_n})
= \emptyset$).
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
We say that $A$ is \emph{comeagre} in $X$ if it is
a complement of a meagre set. Equivalently, a set is comeagre if and only if it
contains a countable intersection of open dense sets.
\end{definition}
% \begin{example}
Every countable set is meagre in any $T_1$ space, so, for example, $\bQ$
is meagre in $\bR$ (although it is dense), which means that the set of
irrationals is comeagre. Another example is...
% \end{example}
\begin{definition}
We say that a topological space $X$ is a \emph{Baire space} if every
comeagre subset of $X$ is dense in $X$ (equivalently, every meagre set has
empty interior).
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
Suppose $X$ is a Baire space. We say that a property $P$ \emph{holds
generically} for a point $x\in X$ if $\{x\in X\mid P\textrm{ holds for
}x\}$ is comeagre in $X$.
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
Let $X$ be a nonempty topological space and let
$A\subseteq X$. The \emph{Banach-Mazur game of $A$}, denoted as
$G^{\star\star}(A)$ is defined as follows: Players $I$ and
$\textit{II}$ take turns in playing nonempty open sets $U_0, V_0,
U_1, V_1,\ldots$ such that $U_0 \supseteq V_0 \supseteq U_1 \supseteq
V_1 \supseteq\ldots$. We say that player $\textit{II}$ wins the game if
$\bigcap_{n}V_n \subseteq A$.
\end{definition}
There is an important theorem on the Banach-Mazur game: $A$ is comeagre
if and only if $\textit{II}$ can always choose sets $V_0, V_1, \ldots$ such that
it wins. Before we prove it we need to define notions necessary to
formalise and prove the theorem.
\begin{definition}
$T$ is \emph{the tree of all legal positions} in the Banach-Mazur game
$G^{\star\star}(A)$ when $T$ consists of all finite sequences $(W_0,
W_1,\ldots, W_n)$, where $W_i$ are nonempty open sets such that
$W_0\supseteq W_1\supseteq\ldots\supseteq W_n$. In other words, $T$ is
a pruned tree on $\{W\subseteq X\mid W \textrm{is open nonempty}\}$.
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
We say that $\sigma$ is \emph{a pruned subtree} of the tree of all legal
positions $T$ if $\sigma\subseteq T$, for any $(W_0, W_1, \ldots,
W_n)\in\sigma, n\ge 0$ there is a $W$ such that $(W_0, W_1,\ldots, W_n,
W)\in\sigma$ (it simply means that there's no finite branch in~$\sigma$) and
$(W_0, W_1,\ldots W_{n-1})\in\sigma$ (every node on a branch is in $\sigma$).
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
Let $\sigma$ be a pruned subtree of the tree of all legal positions $T$. By
$[\sigma]$ we denote \emph{the set of all infinite branches of $\sigma$},
i.e. infinite sequences $(W_0, W_1, \ldots)$ such that $(W_0, W_1, \ldots
W_n)\in \sigma$ for any $n\in \bN$.
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
A \emph{strategy} for $\textit{II}$ in
$G^{\star\star}(A)$ is a pruned subtree $\sigma\subseteq T$ such that
\begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*)]
\item $\sigma$ is nonempty,
\item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n, V_n)\in\sigma$, then for all open
nonempty $U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$, $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n, V_n,
U_{n+1})\in\sigma$,
\item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{n})\in\sigma$, then for a unique $V_n$,
$(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{n}, V_n)\in\sigma$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{definition}
Intuitively, a strategy $\sigma$ works as follows: $I$ starts playing
$U_0$ as any open subset of $X$, then $\textit{II}$ plays unique (by
(iii)) $V_0$ such that $(U_0, V_0)\in\sigma$. Then $I$ responds by
playing any $U_1\subseteq V_0$ and $\textit{II}$ plays unique $V_1$
such that $(U_0, V_0, U_1, V_1)\in\sigma$, etc.
\begin{definition}
A strategy $\sigma$ is a \emph{winning strategy for $\textit{II}$} if for
any game $(U_0, V_0\ldots)\in [\sigma]$ player $\textit{II}$ wins, i.e.
$\bigcap_{n}V_n \subseteq A$.
\end{definition}
Now we can state the key theorem.
\begin{theorem}[Banach-Mazur, Oxtoby]
\label{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}
Let $X$ be a nonempty topological space and let $A\subseteq X$. Then A is
comeagre $\Leftrightarrow$ $\textit{II}$ has a winning strategy in
$G^{\star\star}(A)$.
\end{theorem}
In order to prove it we add an auxiliary definition and lemma.
\begin{definition}
Let $S\subseteq\sigma$ be a pruned subtree of tree of all legal positions
$T$ and let $p=(U_0, V_0,\ldots, V_n)\in S$. We say that S is
\emph{comprehensive for p} if the family $\cV_p = \{V_{n+1}\mid (U_0,
V_0,\ldots, V_n, U_{n+1}, V_{n+1})\in S\}$ (it may be that $n=-1$, which
means $p=\emptyset$) is pairwise disjoint and $\bigcup\cV_p$ is dense in
$V_n$ (where we think that $V_{-1} = X$).
We say that $S$ is \emph{comprehensive} if it is comprehensive for
each $p=(U_0, V_0,\ldots, V_n)\in S$.
\end{definition}
\begin{fact}
If $\sigma$ is a winning strategy for $\mathit{II}$ then
there exists a nonempty comprehensive $S\subseteq\sigma$.
\end{fact}
\begin{proof}
We construct $S$ recursively as follows:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $\emptyset\in S$,
\item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n)\in S$, then $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n,
V_n)\in S$ for the unique $V_n$ given by the strategy $\sigma$,
\item let $p = (U_0, V_0, \ldots, V_n)\in S$. For a possible player $I$'s
move $U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ let $U^\star_{n+1}$ be the unique set
player $\mathit{II}$ would respond with by $\sigma$. Now, by Zorn's
Lemma, let $\cU_p$ be a maximal collection of nonempty open subsets
$U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ such that the set $\{U^\star_{n+1}\mid
U_{n+1}\in\cU_p\}$ is pairwise disjoint. Then put in $S$ all $(U_0,
V_0, \ldots, V_{n}, U_{n+1})$ such that $U_{n+1} \in \cU_p$. This way
$S$ is comprehensive for $p$: the family $\cV_p = \{V_{n+1}\mid (U_0,
V_0,\ldots, V_n, U_{n+1}, V_{n+1})\in S\}$ is exactly
$\{U^\star_{n+1}\mid U_{n+1}\in\cU_p\}$, which is pairwise disjoint and
$\bigcup\cV_p$ is obviously dense in $V_n$ by the maximality of $\cU_p$
-- if there was any open set $\tilde{U}_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ disjoint
from $\bigcup\cV_p$, then $\tilde{U}^{\star}_{n+1}\subseteq
\tilde{U}_{n+1}$ would be also disjoint from $\bigcup\cV_p$, so the
family $\cU_p\cup\{\tilde{U}_{n+1}\}$ would violate the maximality of
$\cU_p$.
\qedhere
\end{enumerate}
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}
Let $S$ be a nonempty comprehensive pruned subtree of a strategy $\sigma$.
Then:
\begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*)]
\item For any open $V_n\subseteq X$ there is at most one $p=(U_0, V_0,
\ldots, U_n, V_n)\in S$.
\item Let $S_n = \{V_n\mid (U_0, V_0, \ldots, V_n)\in S\}$ for $n\in\bN$
(i.e. $S_n$ is a family of all possible choices player $\textit{II}$
can make in its $n$-th move according to $S$). Then $\bigcup S_n$ is
open and dense in $X$.
\item $S_n$ is a family of pairwise disjoint sets.
\end{enumerate}
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
(i): Suppose that there are some $p = (U_0, V_0,\ldots,
U_n, V_n)$, $p'=(U'_0, V'_0, \ldots, U'_n, V'_n)$ such that $V_n
= V'_n$ and $p \neq p'$. Let $k$ be the smallest index such that those
sequences differ. We have two possibilities:
\begin{itemize}
\item $U_k = U'_k$ and $V_k\neq V'_k$ -- this cannot be true simply by
the fact that $S$ is a subset of a strategy (so $V_k$ is unique for
$U_k$). \item $U_k\neq U'_k$: by the comprehensiveness of $S$ we know
that for $q =(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{k-1}, V_{k-1})$ the set $\cV_q$ is
pairwise disjoint. Thus $V_k\cap V'_k=\emptyset$, because $V_k, V'_k\in
\cV_q$. But this leads to a contradiction -- $V_n$ cannot be a nonempty
subset of both $V_k, V'_k$.
\end{itemize}
(ii): The lemma is proved by induction on $n$. For $n=0$ it follows
trivially from the definition of comprehensiveness. Now suppose the
lemma is true for $n$. Then the set $\bigcup_{V_n\in
S_n}\bigcup\cV_{p_{V_n}}$ (where $p_{V_n}$ is given uniquely from
(i)) is dense and open in $X$ by the induction hypothesis. But
$\bigcup S_{n+1}$ is exactly this set, thus it is dense and open in
$X$.
(iii): We will prove it by induction on $n$. Once again, the case $n
= 0$ follows from the comprehensiveness of $S$. Now suppose that the
sets in $S_n$ are pairwise disjoint. Take some $x \in V_{n+1}\in
S_{n+1}$. Of course $\bigcup S_n \supseteq \bigcup S_{n+1}$, thus by
the inductive hypothesis $x\in V_{n}$ for the unique $V_n\in S_n$. It
must be that $V_{n+1}\in \cV_{p_{V_n}}$, because $V_n$ is the only
superset of $V_{n+1}$ in $S_n$. But $\cV_{p_{V_n}}$ is disjoint, so
there is no other $V'_{n+1}\in \cV_{p_{V_n}}$ such that $x\in
V'_{n+1}$. Moreover, there is no such set in
$S_{n+1}\setminus\cV_{p_{V_n}}$, because those sets are disjoint from
$V_{n}$. Hence there is no $V'_{n+1}\in S_{n+1}$ other than $V_n$
such that $x\in V'_{n+1}$. We've chosen $x$ and $V_{n+1}$ arbitrarily,
so $S_{n+1}$ is pairwise disjoint.
\end{proof}
Now we can move to the proof of the Banach-Mazur theorem.
\begin{proof}[Proof of theorem \ref{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}]
$\Rightarrow$: Let $(A_n)$ be a sequence of dense open sets with
$\bigcap_n A_n\subseteq A$. The simply $\textit{II}$ plays $V_n
= U_n\cap A_n$, which is nonempty by the denseness of $A_n$.
$\Leftarrow$: Suppose $\textit{II}$ has a winning strategy $\sigma$.
We will show that $A$ is comeagre. Take a comprehensive $S\subseteq
\sigma$. We claim that $\mathcal{S} = \bigcap_n\bigcup S_n \subseteq
A$. By the lemma~\ref{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}, (ii) sets $\bigcup
S_n$ are open and dense, thus $A$ must be comeagre. Now we prove the
claim towards contradiction.
Suppose there is $x\in \mathcal{S}\setminus A$. By the lemma
\ref{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}, (iii) for any $n$ there is unique
$x\in V_n\in S_n$. It follows that $p_{V_0}\subset
p_{V_1}\subset\ldots$. Now the game $(U_0, V_0, U_1, V_1,\ldots)
= \bigcup_n p_{V_n}\in [S]\subseteq [\sigma]$ is not winning for
player $\textit{II}$, which contradicts the assumption that $\sigma$ is
a winning strategy. \end{proof}
\begin{corollary}
\label{corollary:banach-mazur-basis}
If we add a constraint to the Banach-Mazur game such that players can only
choose basic open sets, then the theorem \ref{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}
still suffices.
\end{corollary}
\begin{proof}
If one adds the word \textit{basic} before each occurrence
of word \textit{open} in previous proofs and theorems then they all
will still be valid (except for $\Rightarrow$, but its an easy fix --
take $V_n$ a basic open subset of $U_n\cap A_n$).
\end{proof}
This corollary will be important in using the theorem in practice --
it's much easier to work with basic open sets rather than any open
sets.
\subsection{Category theory}
In this section we will give a short introduction to the notions of
category theory that will be necessary to generalize the key result of the
paper.
We will use a standard notation. If the reader is interested in detailed
introduction to the category theory, then it's recommended to take a look
at \cite{maclane_1978}. Here we will shortly describe the standard notation.
A \emph{category} $\cC$ consists of the collection of objects (denoted as
$\Obj(\cC)$, but most often simply as $\cC$) and collection of \emph{morphisms}
$\Mor(A, B)$ between each pair of objects $A, B\in \cC$. We require that
for each morphisms $f\colon B\to C$, $g\colon A\to B$ there is a morphism
$f\circ g\colon A\to C$. For every $A\in\cC$ there is an
\emph{identity morphism} $\id_A$ such that for any morphism $f\in \Mor(A, B)$
it follows that $f\circ id_A = \id_B \circ f$.
We say that $f\colon A\to B$ is \emph{isomorphism} if there is (necessarily
unique) morphism $g\colon B\to A$ such that $g\circ f = id_A$ and $f\circ g = id_B$.
Automorphism is an isomorphism where $A = B$.
A \emph{functor} is a ``homeomorphism`` of categories. We say that
$F\colon\cC\to\cD$ is a functor
from category $\cC$ to category $\cD$ if it associates each object $A\in\cC$
with an object $F(A)\in\cD$, associates each morphism $f\colon A\to B$ in
$\cC$ with a morphism $F(f)\colon F(A)\to F(B)$. We also require that
$F(\id_A) = \id_{F(A)}$ and that for any (compatible) morphisms $f, g$ in $\cC$
$F(f\circ g) = F(f) \circ F(g)$.
In category theory we distinguish \emph{covariant} and \emph{contravariant}
functors. Here, we only consider \emph{covariant functors}, so we will simply
say \emph{functor}.
\begin{fact}
\label{fact:functor_iso}
Functor $F\colon\cC\to\cD$ maps isomorphism $f\colon A\to B$ in $\cC$
to the isomorphism $F(f)\colon F(A)\to F(B)$ in $\cD$.
\end{fact}
Notion that will be very important for us is a ``morphism of functors``
which is called \emph{natural transformation}.
\begin{definition}
Let $F, G$ be functors between the categories $\cC, \cD$. A \emph{natural
transformation}
$\tau$ is function that assigns to each object $A$ of $\cC$ a morphism $\tau_A$
in $\Mor(F(A), G(A))$ such that for every morphism $f\colon A\to B$ in $\cC$
the following diagram commutes:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
A \arrow[d, "f"] & F(A) \arrow[r, "\tau_A"] \arrow[d, "F(f)"] & G(A) \arrow[d, "G(f)"] \\
B & F(B) \arrow[r, "\tau_B"] & G(B) \\
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
In category theory, a \emph{diagram} of type $\mathcal{J}$ in category $\cC$
is a functor $D\colon \mathcal{J}\to\cC$. $\mathcal{J}$ is called the
\emph{index category} of $D$. In other words, $D$ is of \emph{shape} $\mathcal{J}$.
For example, $\mathcal{J} = \{-1\leftarrow 0 \rightarrow 1\}$, then a diagram
$D\colon\mathcal{J}\to \cC$ is called a \emph{cospan}. For example,
if $A, B, C$ are objects of $\cC$ and $f\in\Mor(C, A), g\in\Mor(C, B)$, then
the following diagram is a cospan:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
A & & B \\
& C \arrow[ur, "g"'] \arrow[ul, "f"] &
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
\end{definition}
From now we omit explicit definition of the index category, as it is easily
referable from a picture.
\begin{definition}
Let $A, B, C, D$ be objects in the category $\cC$ with morphisms
$e\colon C\to A, f\colon C\to B, g\colon A\to D, h\colon B\to D$ such
that $g\circ e = h\circ f$.
Then the following diagram:
\begin{center}
\begin{tikzcd}
& D & \\
A \arrow[ur, "g"] & & B \arrow[ul, "h"'] \\
& C \arrow[ur, "e"'] \arrow[ul, "f"] &
\end{tikzcd}
\end{center}
is called a \emph{pushout} diagram
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
The \emph{cospan category} of category $\cC$, refered to as $\Cospan(\cC)$,
is the category of cospan diagrams of $\cC$, where morphisms between
two cospans are normal transformations of the underlying functors.
We define \emph{pushout category} analogously and call it $\Pushout(\cC)$.
\end{definition}
TODO: dodać tu przykład?
\end{document}
|