\documentclass[../lic_malinka.tex]{subfiles} \begin{document} \begin{example} Let $\cL$ be the class of all finite linear orderings. Then: \begin{enumerate} \item $\cL$ is a Fraïssé class. \item $\cL$ has canonical amalgamation. \item $\cL$ does not have WHP. \end{enumerate} \end{example} $\cL$ of course has HP and is essentially countable. JEP is also easy, as having two finite linear orderings we can just embed the one with fewer elements into the bigger one. We will show that $\cL$ has canonical amalgamation (CAP). Let $C$ be a finite linear ordered set. We will define $\otimes_C$. Let $A$, $B$ be finite linear orderings that $C$ embeds into. We may suppose that $C = A\cap B$. Then we define an ordering on $D = A\cup B$. For $d,e \in D$, let $d\le_D e$ if one of the following hold: \begin{itemize} \item $d,e\in A$ and $d\le_A e$, \item $d,e\in B$ and $d\le_B e$, \item $d\in A, e\in B$ and there is $c\in C$ such that $d\le_A c$ and $c\le_B e$, \item $d\in B, e\in A$ and there is $c\in C$ such that $d\le_B c$ and $c\le_A e$, \item $d\in A, e\in B$ and for all $c\in C$ $d\le_A c\Leftrightarrow e\le_B c$ \end{itemize} One can imagine that $D$ can be constructed by laying elements of $C$ in a row and putting elements of $A$ and $B$ appropriately between elements of $C$ with all elements of $A$ to the left and all elements of $B$ to the right between two adjacent elements of $C$. This clearly is a canonical amalgamation. \vspace{0.5cm} \begin{figure}[h] \centering \begin{tikzpicture} \draw[->,thick] (-1.5,0)--(1.5,0) node[right]{$C$}; \foreach \x in {0,...,2} \node at ({-1.5+3/4*(1+\x)},0)[circle,fill=green,inner sep=2pt]{}; \draw[->] (-1,0.5) -- (-3,1.5); \draw[->] (1,0.5) -- (3,1.5); \draw[->,thick] (-6, 2)--(0,2) node[right]{$A$}; \foreach \x in {0,...,7} \node at ({-6 + 6/9 * (\x+1)},2)[rectangle,fill=red, inner sep=2pt]{}; \foreach \x in {2,5,6} \node at ({-6 + 6/9 * (\x+1)},2)[circle,fill=green, inner sep=2pt]{}; \draw[->] (-3,2.5) -- (-2,3.5); \draw[->,thick] (1, 2)--(6,2) node[right]{$B$}; \foreach \x in {0,2,4,6} \node at ({1+5/8*(\x+1)},2)[star,fill=blue, inner sep=2pt]{}; \foreach \x in {1, 3, 5} \node at ({1+5/8*(\x+1)},2)[circle,fill=green, inner sep=2pt]{}; \draw[->] (3,2.5) -- (2,3.5); \draw[->,thick] (-5, 4)--(5,4) node[right]{$D$}; % \foreach \x in {0,...,11} % \node at ({-5+10/13*(\x+1)}, 4)[circle,fill=black,inner sep=2pt]{}; \foreach \x in {3,7,9} \node at ({-5+10/13*(\x+1)}, 4)[circle,fill=green,inner sep=2pt]{}; \foreach \x in {0,1,4,5,10} \node at ({-5+10/13*(\x+1)}, 4)[rectangle,fill=red,inner sep=2pt]{}; \foreach \x in {2,6,8,11} \node at ({-5+10/13*(\x+1)}, 4)[star,fill=blue,inner sep=2pt]{}; \end{tikzpicture} \caption{Visual representation of the construction.} \end{figure} \vspace{0.5cm} On the other hand $\cL$ cannot have $WHP$. This follows from the fact that that only automorphism of a finite linear ordering is identity, so we cannot extend a partial automorphism sending exactly one element to some distinct element. However, in this case, generic automorphism exists which was shown by Truss \cite{truss_gen_aut}. \begin{definition} Let $X$ be a set. A ternary relation $\le^C \subseteq X^3$ is a \emph{cyclic order}, where we denote $(a,b,c)\in{\le^C}$ as $a\le^{C}_{b}c$ (or simply $a\le_bc$ when there's only one relation in the context), when it satisfies the following properties: \begin{itemize} \item If $a\le_bc$, then $b\le_ca$. \item If $a\le_bc$, then not $c\le_ba$. \item If $a\le_bc$ and $a\le_cd$, then $a\le_bd$. \item If $a,b,c$ are pairwise distinct, then either $a\le_bc$ or $c\le_ba$. \end{itemize} \end{definition} It is easy to visualize a cyclic ordering as a directed (\textit{nomen omen}) cycle. For example, a 11-element cyclic order could be drawn like this: \begin{figure}[h] \centering \begin{tikzpicture} \def \n {11} \def \radius {3cm} \def \margin {10} \foreach \s in {1,...,\n} { \node[draw, circle] at ({360/\n * (\s - 1)}:\radius) {}; \draw[->, >=latex] ({360/\n * (\s - 1)+\margin}:\radius) arc ({360/\n * (\s - 1)+\margin}:{360/\n * (\s)-\margin}:\radius); } \node[draw, circle, fill=green] at ({360/\n * (1 - 1)}:\radius) {}; \node[draw, circle, fill=blue] at ({360/\n * (5 - 1)}:\radius) {}; \node[draw, circle, fill=red] at ({360/\n * (9 - 1)}:\radius) {}; \end{tikzpicture} \end{figure} For three elements $a, b, c$ we say that $a\le_bc$ if after ''cutting'' the cycle at $b$ we have a path from $a$ to $c$. In this particular example we can say that the green element is red-element-smaller than the blue one. \begin{example} The class $\cC$ of all finite cyclic orders is a Fraïssé class, but does not have WHP or CAP. \end{example} It is not hard to show that $\cC$ is indeed the Fraïssé class. As usual, the hardest part is showing AP, which in this case is done analogously to the linear orders. The Fraïssé limit of $\cC$ is a countable unit circle. $\cC$ hasn't WHP by the similar argument to this for linear orderings. Imagine a cycling order of three elements and a partial automorphism with one fixed point and moving second element to the third. This cannot be extended to automorphism of any finite cyclic order. Also, $\cC$ cannot have CAP. A reason to that is that it do not admit canonical amalgamation over the empty structure see this by taking 1-element cyclic order and 3-element cyclic order with automorphism other than identity). In contrast to linear orderings the Fraïssé limit $\Sigma = \Flim{\cC}$ has no generic automorphism. Consider the set $A$ of automorphisms of $\Sigma$ with at least one finite orbit of size greater than $1$. It is open, not dense and closed on conjugation. Openness follows from the fact that all finite orbits of a given automorphism have the same size. Thus $A$ can be represented as a union of basic set generated by finite cycles of length greater than $1$. It is not dense, as it has empty intersection with basic set generated by identity of a single element. It is also closed on taking conjugation, as the order of elements does not change when conjugating. Thus there cannot be a dense conjugacy class in $\Aut(\Sigma)$ and so there's no generic automorphism. \begin{example} The class of all finitely generated vector spaces over a countable field $\cV$ is a Fraïssé class with WHP and CAP. \end{example} The prove of this is relatively easy, knowing that there is essentially one vector space of every finite dimension and that every linear independent subset of a vector space can be extended to a basis of this space. The Fraïssé limit of $\cV$ is the $\omega$-dimensional vector space. Thus, by our key Theorem \ref{theorem:key-theorem} we know that it has a generic automorphism. \begin{example} The class of all finite graphs $\cG$ is a Fraïssé class with WHP and free amalgamation. \end{example} We have already shown this fact. Thus get that the random graph has a generic automorphism. \begin{example} A $K_n$-free graph is a graph with no $n$-clique as its subgraph. Let $\cG_n$ be the class of finite \emph{$K_n$-free} graphs. $\cG_n$ is a Fraïssé class with WHP and free amalgamation. \end{example} Showing that $\cG_n$ is indeed a Fraïssé class is almost the same as in normal graphs, together with free amalgamation. WHP is trickier and the proof can be seen in \cite{eppa_presentation} Theorem 3.6. Hence, $\Flim(\cG_n)$ has a generic automorphism. \end{document}