aboutsummaryrefslogtreecommitdiff
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
-rw-r--r--lic_malinka.pdfbin419889 -> 419937 bytes
-rw-r--r--lic_malinka.tex1045
-rw-r--r--sections/conj_classes.tex251
-rw-r--r--sections/fraisse_classes.tex451
-rw-r--r--sections/introduction.tex5
-rw-r--r--sections/preliminaries.tex347
6 files changed, 1060 insertions, 1039 deletions
diff --git a/lic_malinka.pdf b/lic_malinka.pdf
index 4d7d77d..dc875f1 100644
--- a/lic_malinka.pdf
+++ b/lic_malinka.pdf
Binary files differ
diff --git a/lic_malinka.tex b/lic_malinka.tex
index 4ce39e0..96f97a3 100644
--- a/lic_malinka.tex
+++ b/lic_malinka.tex
@@ -37,6 +37,8 @@
\usepackage[notref, notcite]{showkeys}
\usepackage[cmtip,arrow]{xy}
+\usepackage{subfiles}
+
\DeclareMathOperator{\Aut}{Aut}
\DeclareMathOperator{\Hom}{Hom}
\DeclareMathOperator{\Stab}{Stab}
@@ -107,7 +109,6 @@
\newcommand{\xqed}[1]{% \leavevmode\unskip\penalty9999 \hbox{}\nobreak\hfill
\quad\hbox{\ensuremath{#1}}}
-
\title{Tytuł}
\author{Franciszek Malinka}
@@ -116,1050 +117,16 @@
Abstract
\end{abstract}
\section{Introduction}
+ \subfile{sections/introduction}
\section{Preliminaries}
- \subsection{Descriptive set theory}
- \begin{definition}
- Suppose $X$ is a topological space and $A\subseteq X$.
- We say that $A$ is \emph{meagre} in $X$ if $A = \bigcup_{n\in\bN}A_n$,
- where $A_n$ are nowhere dense subsets of $X$ (i.e. $\Int(\bar{A_n})
- = \emptyset$).
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- We say that $A$ is \emph{comeagre} in $X$ if it is
- a complement of a meagre set. Equivalently, a set is comeagre if and only if it
- contains a countable intersection of open dense sets.
- \end{definition}
-
- % \begin{example}
- Every countable set is meagre in any $T_1$ space, so, for example, $\bQ$
- is meagre in $\bR$ (although it is dense), which means that the set of
- irrationals is comeagre. Another example is...
- % \end{example}
-
- \begin{definition}
- We say that a topological space $X$ is a \emph{Baire space} if every
- comeagre subset of $X$ is dense in $X$ (equivalently, every meagre set has
- empty interior).
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- Suppose $X$ is a Baire space. We say that a property $P$ \emph{holds
- generically} for a point $x\in X$ if $\{x\in X\mid P\textrm{ holds for
- }x\}$ is comeagre in $X$.
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- Let $X$ be a nonempty topological space and let
- $A\subseteq X$. The \emph{Banach-Mazur game of $A$}, denoted as
- $G^{\star\star}(A)$ is defined as follows: Players $I$ and
- $\textit{II}$ take turns in playing nonempty open sets $U_0, V_0,
- U_1, V_1,\ldots$ such that $U_0 \supseteq V_0 \supseteq U_1 \supseteq
- V_1 \supseteq\ldots$. We say that player $\textit{II}$ wins the game if
- $\bigcap_{n}V_n \subseteq A$.
- \end{definition}
-
- There is an important theorem on the Banach-Mazur game: $A$ is comeagre
- if and only if $\textit{II}$ can always choose sets $V_0, V_1, \ldots$ such that
- it wins. Before we prove it we need to define notions necessary to
- formalise and prove the theorem.
-
- \begin{definition}
- $T$ is \emph{the tree of all legal positions} in the Banach-Mazur game
- $G^{\star\star}(A)$ when $T$ consists of all finite sequences $(W_0,
- W_1,\ldots, W_n)$, where $W_i$ are nonempty open sets such that
- $W_0\supseteq W_1\supseteq\ldots\supseteq W_n$. In other words, $T$ is
- a pruned tree on $\{W\subseteq X\mid W \textrm{is open nonempty}\}$.
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- We say that $\sigma$ is \emph{a pruned subtree} of the tree of all legal
- positions $T$ if $\sigma\subseteq T$, for any $(W_0, W_1, \ldots,
- W_n)\in\sigma, n\ge 0$ there is a $W$ such that $(W_0, W_1,\ldots, W_n,
- W)\in\sigma$ (it simply means that there's no finite branch in~$\sigma$) and
- $(W_0, W_1,\ldots W_{n-1})\in\sigma$ (every node on a branch is in $\sigma$).
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- Let $\sigma$ be a pruned subtree of the tree of all legal positions $T$. By
- $[\sigma]$ we denote \emph{the set of all infinite branches of $\sigma$},
- i.e. infinite sequences $(W_0, W_1, \ldots)$ such that $(W_0, W_1, \ldots
- W_n)\in \sigma$ for any $n\in \bN$.
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- A \emph{strategy} for $\textit{II}$ in
- $G^{\star\star}(A)$ is a pruned subtree $\sigma\subseteq T$ such that
- \begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*)]
- \item $\sigma$ is nonempty,
- \item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n, V_n)\in\sigma$, then for all open
- nonempty $U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$, $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n, V_n,
- U_{n+1})\in\sigma$,
- \item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{n})\in\sigma$, then for a unique $V_n$,
- $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{n}, V_n)\in\sigma$.
- \end{enumerate}
- \end{definition}
-
- Intuitively, a strategy $\sigma$ works as follows: $I$ starts playing
- $U_0$ as any open subset of $X$, then $\textit{II}$ plays unique (by
- (iii)) $V_0$ such that $(U_0, V_0)\in\sigma$. Then $I$ responds by
- playing any $U_1\subseteq V_0$ and $\textit{II}$ plays unique $V_1$
- such that $(U_0, V_0, U_1, V_1)\in\sigma$, etc.
-
- \begin{definition}
- A strategy $\sigma$ is a \emph{winning strategy for $\textit{II}$} if for
- any game $(U_0, V_0\ldots)\in [\sigma]$ player $\textit{II}$ wins, i.e.
- $\bigcap_{n}V_n \subseteq A$.
- \end{definition}
-
- Now we can state the key theorem.
-
- \begin{theorem}[Banach-Mazur, Oxtoby]
- \label{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}
- Let $X$ be a nonempty topological space and let $A\subseteq X$. Then A is
- comeagre $\Leftrightarrow$ $\textit{II}$ has a winning strategy in
- $G^{\star\star}(A)$.
- \end{theorem}
-
- In order to prove it we add an auxiliary definition and lemma.
- \begin{definition}
- Let $S\subseteq\sigma$ be a pruned subtree of tree of all legal positions
- $T$ and let $p=(U_0, V_0,\ldots, V_n)\in S$. We say that S is
- \emph{comprehensive for p} if the family $\cV_p = \{V_{n+1}\mid (U_0,
- V_0,\ldots, V_n, U_{n+1}, V_{n+1})\in S\}$ (it may be that $n=-1$, which
- means $p=\emptyset$) is pairwise disjoint and $\bigcup\cV_p$ is dense in
- $V_n$ (where we think that $V_{-1} = X$).
- We say that $S$ is \emph{comprehensive} if it is comprehensive for
- each $p=(U_0, V_0,\ldots, V_n)\in S$.
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{fact}
- If $\sigma$ is a winning strategy for $\mathit{II}$ then
- there exists a nonempty comprehensive $S\subseteq\sigma$.
- \end{fact}
-
- \begin{proof}
- We construct $S$ recursively as follows:
- \begin{enumerate}
- \item $\emptyset\in S$,
- \item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n)\in S$, then $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n,
- V_n)\in S$ for the unique $V_n$ given by the strategy $\sigma$,
- \item let $p = (U_0, V_0, \ldots, V_n)\in S$. For a possible player $I$'s
- move $U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ let $U^\star_{n+1}$ be the unique set
- player $\mathit{II}$ would respond with by $\sigma$. Now, by Zorn's
- Lemma, let $\cU_p$ be a maximal collection of nonempty open subsets
- $U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ such that the set $\{U^\star_{n+1}\mid
- U_{n+1}\in\cU_p\}$ is pairwise disjoint. Then put in $S$ all $(U_0,
- V_0, \ldots, V_{n}, U_{n+1})$ such that $U_{n+1} \in \cU_p$. This way
- $S$ is comprehensive for $p$: the family $\cV_p = \{V_{n+1}\mid (U_0,
- V_0,\ldots, V_n, U_{n+1}, V_{n+1})\in S\}$ is exactly
- $\{U^\star_{n+1}\mid U_{n+1}\in\cU_p\}$, which is pairwise disjoint and
- $\bigcup\cV_p$ is obviously dense in $V_n$ by the maximality of $\cU_p$
- -- if there was any open set $\tilde{U}_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ disjoint
- from $\bigcup\cV_p$, then $\tilde{U}^{\star}_{n+1}\subseteq
- \tilde{U}_{n+1}$ would be also disjoint from $\bigcup\cV_p$, so the
- family $\cU_p\cup\{\tilde{U}_{n+1}\}$ would violate the maximality of
- $\cU_p$.
- \qedhere
- \end{enumerate}
- \end{proof}
-
- \begin{lemma}
- \label{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}
- Let $S$ be a nonempty comprehensive pruned subtree of a strategy $\sigma$.
- Then:
- \begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*)]
- \item For any open $V_n\subseteq X$ there is at most one $p=(U_0, V_0,
- \ldots, U_n, V_n)\in S$.
- \item Let $S_n = \{V_n\mid (U_0, V_0, \ldots, V_n)\in S\}$ for $n\in\bN$
- (i.e. $S_n$ is a family of all possible choices player $\textit{II}$
- can make in its $n$-th move according to $S$). Then $\bigcup S_n$ is
- open and dense in $X$.
- \item $S_n$ is a family of pairwise disjoint sets.
- \end{enumerate}
- \end{lemma}
-
- \begin{proof}
- (i): Suppose that there are some $p = (U_0, V_0,\ldots,
- U_n, V_n)$, $p'=(U'_0, V'_0, \ldots, U'_n, V'_n)$ such that $V_n
- = V'_n$ and $p \neq p'$. Let $k$ be the smallest index such that those
- sequences differ. We have two possibilities:
- \begin{itemize}
- \item $U_k = U'_k$ and $V_k\neq V'_k$ -- this cannot be true simply by
- the fact that $S$ is a subset of a strategy (so $V_k$ is unique for
- $U_k$). \item $U_k\neq U'_k$: by the comprehensiveness of $S$ we know
- that for $q =(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{k-1}, V_{k-1})$ the set $\cV_q$ is
- pairwise disjoint. Thus $V_k\cap V'_k=\emptyset$, because $V_k, V'_k\in
- \cV_q$. But this leads to a contradiction -- $V_n$ cannot be a nonempty
- subset of both $V_k, V'_k$.
- \end{itemize}
-
- (ii): The lemma is proved by induction on $n$. For $n=0$ it follows
- trivially from the definition of comprehensiveness. Now suppose the
- lemma is true for $n$. Then the set $\bigcup_{V_n\in
- S_n}\bigcup\cV_{p_{V_n}}$ (where $p_{V_n}$ is given uniquely from
- (i)) is dense and open in $X$ by the induction hypothesis. But
- $\bigcup S_{n+1}$ is exactly this set, thus it is dense and open in
- $X$.
-
- (iii): We will prove it by induction on $n$. Once again, the case $n
- = 0$ follows from the comprehensiveness of $S$. Now suppose that the
- sets in $S_n$ are pairwise disjoint. Take some $x \in V_{n+1}\in
- S_{n+1}$. Of course $\bigcup S_n \supseteq \bigcup S_{n+1}$, thus by
- the inductive hypothesis $x\in V_{n}$ for the unique $V_n\in S_n$. It
- must be that $V_{n+1}\in \cV_{p_{V_n}}$, because $V_n$ is the only
- superset of $V_{n+1}$ in $S_n$. But $\cV_{p_{V_n}}$ is disjoint, so
- there is no other $V'_{n+1}\in \cV_{p_{V_n}}$ such that $x\in
- V'_{n+1}$. Moreover, there is no such set in
- $S_{n+1}\setminus\cV_{p_{V_n}}$, because those sets are disjoint from
- $V_{n}$. Hence there is no $V'_{n+1}\in S_{n+1}$ other than $V_n$
- such that $x\in V'_{n+1}$. We've chosen $x$ and $V_{n+1}$ arbitrarily,
- so $S_{n+1}$ is pairwise disjoint.
- \end{proof}
-
- Now we can move to the proof of the Banach-Mazur theorem.
-
- \begin{proof}[Proof of theorem \ref{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}]
- $\Rightarrow$: Let $(A_n)$ be a sequence of dense open sets with
- $\bigcap_n A_n\subseteq A$. The simply $\textit{II}$ plays $V_n
- = U_n\cap A_n$, which is nonempty by the denseness of $A_n$.
-
- $\Leftarrow$: Suppose $\textit{II}$ has a winning strategy $\sigma$.
- We will show that $A$ is comeagre. Take a comprehensive $S\subseteq
- \sigma$. We claim that $\mathcal{S} = \bigcap_n\bigcup S_n \subseteq
- A$. By the lemma~\ref{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}, (ii) sets $\bigcup
- S_n$ are open and dense, thus $A$ must be comeagre. Now we prove the
- claim towards contradiction.
-
- Suppose there is $x\in \mathcal{S}\setminus A$. By the lemma
- \ref{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}, (iii) for any $n$ there is unique
- $x\in V_n\in S_n$. It follows that $p_{V_0}\subset
- p_{V_1}\subset\ldots$. Now the game $(U_0, V_0, U_1, V_1,\ldots)
- = \bigcup_n p_{V_n}\in [S]\subseteq [\sigma]$ is not winning for
- player $\textit{II}$, which contradicts the assumption that $\sigma$ is
- a winning strategy. \end{proof}
-
- \begin{corollary}
- \label{corollary:banach-mazur-basis}
- If we add a constraint to the Banach-Mazur game such that players can only
- choose basic open sets, then the theorem \ref{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}
- still suffices.
- \end{corollary}
-
- \begin{proof}
- If one adds the word \textit{basic} before each occurrence
- of word \textit{open} in previous proofs and theorems then they all
- will still be valid (except for $\Rightarrow$, but its an easy fix --
- take $V_n$ a basic open subset of $U_n\cap A_n$).
- \end{proof}
-
- This corollary will be important in using the theorem in practice --
- it's much easier to work with basic open sets rather than any open
- sets.
-
- \subsection{Category theory}
-
- In this section we will give a short introduction to the notions of
- category theory that will be necessary to generalize the key result of the
- paper.
-
- We will use a standard notation. If the reader is interested in detailed
- introduction to the category theory, then it's recommended to take a look
- at \cite{maclane_1978}. Here we will shortly describe the standard notation.
-
- A \emph{category} $\cC$ consists of the collection of objects (denoted as
- $\Obj(\cC)$, but most often simply as $\cC$) and collection of \emph{morphisms}
- $\Mor(A, B)$ between each pair of objects $A, B\in \cC$. We require that
- for each morphisms $f\colon B\to C$, $g\colon A\to B$ there is a morphism
- $f\circ g\colon A\to C$. For every $A\in\cC$ there is an
- \emph{identity morphism} $\id_A$ such that for any morphism $f\in \Mor(A, B)$
- it follows that $f\circ id_A = \id_B \circ f$.
-
- We say that $f\colon A\to B$ is \emph{isomorphism} if there is (necessarily
- unique) morphism $g\colon B\to A$ such that $g\circ f = id_A$ and $f\circ g = id_B$.
- Automorphism is an isomorphism where $A = B$.
-
- A \emph{functor} is a ``homeomorphism`` of categories. We say that
- $F\colon\cC\to\cD$ is a functor
- from category $\cC$ to category $\cD$ if it associates each object $A\in\cC$
- with an object $F(A)\in\cD$, associates each morphism $f\colon A\to B$ in
- $\cC$ with a morphism $F(f)\colon F(A)\to F(B)$. We also require that
- $F(\id_A) = \id_{F(A)}$ and that for any (compatible) morphisms $f, g$ in $\cC$
- $F(f\circ g) = F(f) \circ F(g)$.
-
- In category theory we distinguish \emph{covariant} and \emph{contravariant}
- functors. Here, we only consider \emph{covariant functors}, so we will simply
- say \emph{functor}.
-
- \begin{fact}
- \label{fact:functor_iso}
- Functor $F\colon\cC\to\cD$ maps isomorphism $f\colon A\to B$ in $\cC$
- to the isomorphism $F(f)\colon F(A)\to F(B)$ in $\cD$.
- \end{fact}
-
- Notion that will be very important for us is a ``morphism of functors``
- which is called \emph{natural transformation}.
- \begin{definition}
- Let $F, G$ be functors between the categories $\cC, \cD$. A \emph{natural
- transformation}
- $\tau$ is function that assigns to each object $A$ of $\cC$ a morphism $\tau_A$
- in $\Mor(F(A), G(A))$ such that for every morphism $f\colon A\to B$ in $\cC$
- the following diagram commutes:
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- A \arrow[d, "f"] & F(A) \arrow[r, "\tau_A"] \arrow[d, "F(f)"] & G(A) \arrow[d, "G(f)"] \\
- B & F(B) \arrow[r, "\tau_B"] & G(B) \\
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- In category theory, a \emph{diagram} of type $\mathcal{J}$ in category $\cC$
- is a functor $D\colon \mathcal{J}\to\cC$. $\mathcal{J}$ is called the
- \emph{index category} of $D$. In other words, $D$ is of \emph{shape} $\mathcal{J}$.
-
- For example, $\mathcal{J} = \{-1\leftarrow 0 \rightarrow 1\}$, then a diagram
- $D\colon\mathcal{J}\to \cC$ is called a \emph{cospan}. For example,
- if $A, B, C$ are objects of $\cC$ and $f\in\Mor(C, A), g\in\Mor(C, B)$, then
- the following diagram is a cospan:
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- A & & B \\
- & C \arrow[ur, "g"'] \arrow[ul, "f"] &
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
- \end{definition}
-
- From now we omit explicit definition of the index category, as it is easily
- referable from a picture.
-
- \begin{definition}
- Let $A, B, C, D$ be objects in the category $\cC$ with morphisms
- $e\colon C\to A, f\colon C\to B, g\colon A\to D, h\colon B\to D$ such
- that $g\circ e = h\circ f$.
- Then the following diagram:
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- & D & \\
- A \arrow[ur, "g"] & & B \arrow[ul, "h"'] \\
- & C \arrow[ur, "e"'] \arrow[ul, "f"] &
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- is called a \emph{pushout} diagram
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- The \emph{cospan category} of category $\cC$, refered to as $\Cospan(\cC)$,
- is the category of cospan diagrams of $\cC$, where morphisms between
- two cospans are normal transformations of the underlying functors.
-
- We define \emph{pushout category} analogously and call it $\Pushout(\cC)$.
- \end{definition}
-
- TODO: dodać tu przykład?
+ \subfile{sections/preliminaries}
\section{Fraïssé classes}
-
- In this section we will take a closer look at classes of finitely
- generated structures with some characteristic properties. More
- specifically, we will describe a concept developed by a French
- mathematician Roland Fraïssé called Fraïssé limit.
-
- \subsection{Definitions}
- \begin{definition}
- Let $L$ be a signature and $M$ be an $L$-structure. The \emph{age} of $M$ is
- the class $\bK$ of all finitely generated structures that embeds into $M$.
- The age of $M$ is also associated with class of all structures embeddable in
- $M$ \emph{up to isomorphism}.
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- We say that $M$ has \emph{countable age} when its age has countably many
- isomorphism types of finitely generated structures.
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated structures. $\bK$ has
- \emph{hereditary property (HP)} if for any $A\in\bK$, any finitely generated
- substructure $B$ of $A$ it holds that $B\in\bK$.
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{definition}
- Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated structures. We say that $\bK$ has
- \emph{joint embedding property (JEP)} if for any $A, B\in\bK$ there is a
- structure $C\in\bK$ such that both $A$ and $B$ embed in $C$.
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- & C & \\
- A \arrow[ur, dashed, "f"] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed, "g"']
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- In terms of category theory, this is a \emph{span} in category $\bK$.
- \end{definition}
-
- Fraïssé has shown fundamental theories regarding age of a structure, one of
- them being the following one:
-
- \begin{fact}
- \label{fact:age_is_hpjep}
- Suppose $L$ is a signature and $\bK$ is a nonempty finite or countable set
- of finitely generated $L$-structures. Then $\bK$ has the HP and JEP if
- and only if $\bK$ is the age of some finite or countable structure.
- \end{fact}
-
- Beside the HP and JEP Fraïssé has distinguished one more property of the
- class $\bK$, namely amalgamation property.
-
- \begin{definition}
- Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated $L$-structures. We say that $\bK$
- has the \emph{amalgamation property (AP)} if for any $A, B, C\in\bK$ and
- embeddings $e\colon C\to A, f\colon C\to B$ there exists $D\in\bK$ together
- with embeddings $g\colon A\to D$ and $h\colon A\to D$ such that
- $g\circ e = h\circ f$.
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- & D & \\
- A \arrow[ur, dashed, "g"] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed, "h"'] \\
- & C \arrow[ur, "f"'] \arrow[ul, "e"]
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
- \end{definition}
-
- In terms of category theory, amalgamation over some structure $C$ is a
- pushout diagram.
-
- \begin{definition}
- Let $M$ be an $L$-structure. $M$ is \emph{ultrahomogeneous} if every
- isomorphism between finitely generated substructures of $M$ extends to an
- automorphism of $M$.
- \end{definition}
-
- Having those definitions we can provide the main Fraïssé theorem.
-
- \begin{theorem}[Fraïssé theorem]
- \label{theorem:fraisse_thm}
- Let L be a countable language and let $\bK$ be a nonempty countable set of
- finitely generated $L$-structures which has HP, JEP and AP. Then $\bK$ is
- the age of a countable, ultrahomogeneous $L$-structure $M$. Moreover, $M$ is
- unique up to isomorphism. We say that $M$ is a \emph{Fraïssé limit} of $\bK$
- and denote this by $M = \Flim(\bK)$.
- \end{theorem}
-
- This is a well known theorem. One can read a proof of this theorem in Wilfrid
- Hodges' classical book \textit{Model Theory}~\cite{hodges_1993}. In the proof
- of this theorem appears another, equally important \ref{lemma:weak_ultrahom}.
-
- \begin{definition}
- We say that an $L$-structure $M$ is \emph{weakly ultrahomogeneous} if for any
- $A, B$ finitely generated substructures of $M$ such that $A\subseteq B$ and
- an embedding $f\colon A\to M$ there is an embedding $g\colon B\to M$ which
- extends $f$.
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- A \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "f"] & D \\
- B \arrow[ur, dashed, "g"']
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{lemma}
- \label{lemma:weak_ultrahom}
- A countable structure is ultrahomogeneous if and only if it is weakly
- ultrahomogeneous.
- \end{lemma}
-
- This lemma will play a major role in the later parts of the paper. Weak
- ultrahomogeneity is an easier and more intuitive property and it will prove
- useful when recursively constructing the generic automorphism of a Fraïssé
- limit.
-
- % \begin{fact} If $\bK$ is a uniformly locally finite Fraïssé class, then
- % $\Flim(\bK)$ is $\aleph_0$-categorical and has quantifier elimination.
- % \end{fact}
-
- \subsection{Random graph}
-
- In this section we'll take a closer look on a class of finite unordered graphs,
- which is a Fraïssé class.
-
- The language of unordered graphs $L$ consists of a single binary
- relational symbol $E$. If $G$ is an $L$-structure then we call it a
- \emph{graph}, and its elements $\emph{vertices}$. If for some vertices
- $u, v\in G$ we have $G\models uEv$ then we say that there is an $\emph{edge}$
- connecting $u$ and $v$. If $G\models \forall x\forall y (xEy\leftrightarrow yEx)$
- then we say that $G$ is an \emph{unordered graph}. From now on we omit the word
- \textit{unordered} and graphs as unordered.
-
- \begin{proposition}
- Let $\cG$ be the class of all finite graphs. $\cG$ is a Fraïssé class.
- \end{proposition}
- \begin{proof}
- $\cG$ is of course countable (up to isomorphism) and has the HP
- (graph substructure is also a graph). It has JEP: having two finite graphs
- $G_1,G_2$ take their disjoint union $G_1\sqcup G_2$ as the extension of them
- both. $\cG$ has the AP. Having graphs $A, B, C$, where $B$ and $C$ are
- supergraphs of $A$, we can assume without loss of generality, that
- $(B\setminus A) \cap (C\setminus A) = \emptyset$. Then
- $A\sqcup (B\setminus A)\sqcup (C\setminus A)$ is the graph we're looking
- for (with edges as in B and C and without any edges between $B\setminus A$
- and $C\setminus A$).
- \end{proof}
-
- \begin{definition}
- The \emph{random graph} is the Fraïssé limit of the class of finite graphs
- $\cG$ denoted by $\FrGr = \Flim(\cG)$.
- \end{definition}
-
- The concept of the random graph emerges independently in many fields of
- mathematics. For example, one can construct the graph by choosing at random
- for each pair of vertices if they should be connected or not. It turns out
- that the graph constructed this way is isomorphic to the random graph with
- probability 1.
-
- The random graph $\FrGr$ has one particular property that is unique to the
- random graph.
-
- \begin{fact}[random graph property]
- For each finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq \FrGr$ there exists $v\in\FrGr\setminus (X\cup Y)$
- such that $\forall u\in X (vEu)$ and $\forall u\in Y (\neg vEu)$.
- \end{fact}
- \begin{proof}
- Take any finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq\FrGr$. Let $G_{XY}$ be the
- subgraph of $\FrGr$ induced by the $X\cup Y$. Let $H = G_{XY}\cup \{w\}$,
- where $w$ is a new vertex that does not appear in $G_{XY}$. Also, $w$ is connected to
- all vertices of $G_{XY}$ that come from $X$ and to none of those that come
- from $Y$. This graph is of course finite, so it is embeddable in $\FrGr$.
- Without loss of generality assume that this embedding is simply inclusion.
- Let $f$ be the partial isomorphism from $X\sqcup Y$ to $H$, with $X$ and
- $Y$ projected to the part of $H$ that come from $X$ and $Y$ respectively.
- By the ultrahomogeneity of $\FrGr$ this isomorphism extends to an automorphism
- $\sigma\in\Aut(\FrGr)$. Then $v = \sigma^{-1}(w)$ is the vertex we sought.
- \end{proof}
-
- \begin{fact}
- If a countable graph $G$ has the random graph property, then it is
- isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
- \end{fact}
- \begin{proof}
- Enumerate vertices of both graphs: $\FrGr = \{a_1, a_2\ldots\}$ and $G
- = \{b_1, b_2\ldots\}$.
- We will construct a chain of partial isomorphisms $f_n\colon \FrGr\to G$
- such that $\emptyset = f_0\subseteq f_1\subseteq f_2\subseteq\ldots$ and $a_n \in
- \dom(f_n)$ and $b_n\in\rng(f_n)$.
-
- Suppose we have $f_n$. We seek $b\in G$ such that $f_n\cup \{\langle
- a_{n+1}, b\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism.
- If $a_{n+1}\in\dom{f_n}$, then simply $b = f_n(a_{n+1})$. Otherwise,
- let $X = \{a\in\FrGr\mid
- aE_{\FrGr} a_{n+1}\}\cap \dom{f_n}, Y = X^{c}\cap \dom{f_n}$, i.e. $X$ are
- vertices of $\dom{f_n}$ that are connected with $a_{n+1}$ in $\FrGr$ and
- $Y$ are those vertices that are not connected with $a_{n+1}$. Let $b$ be
- a vertex of $G$ that is connected to all vertices of $f_n[X]$ and to none
- $f_n[Y]$ (it exists by the random graph property). Then $f_n\cup \{\langle
- a_{n+1}, b\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism. We find $a$ for the
- $b_{n+1}$ in the similar manner, so that $f_{n+1} = f_n\cup \{\langle
- a_{n+1}, b\rangle, \langle a, b_{n+1}\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism.
-
- Finally, $f = \bigcup^{\infty}_{n=0}f_n$ is an isomorphism between $\FrGr$
- and $G$. Take any $a, b\in \FrGr$. Then for some big enough $n$ we have
- that $aE_{\FrGr}b\Leftrightarrow f_n(a)E_{G}f_n(b) \Leftrightarrow f(a)E_{G}f(b)$.
- \end{proof}
-
- Using this fact one can show that the graph constructed in the probabilistic
- manner is in fact isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
-
- \begin{definition} We say that a Fraïssé class $\bK$ has \emph{weak
- Hrushovski property} (\emph{WHP}) if for every $A\in \bK$ and an isomorphism
- of its substructures $p\colon A\to A$ (also called a partial automorphism of $A$),
- there is some $B\in \bK$ such
- that $p$ can be extended to an automorphism of $B$, i.e.\ there is an
- embedding $i\colon A\to B$ and a $\bar p\in \Aut(B)$ such that the following
- diagram commutes:
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- B\ar[r,dashed,"\bar p"]&B\\
- A\ar[u,dashed,"i"]\ar[r,"p"]&A\ar[u,dashed,"i"]
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{proposition}
- \label{proposition:finite-graphs-whp}
- The class of finite graphs $\cG$ has the weak Hrushovski property.
- \end{proposition}
-
- \begin{proof}
- It may be there some day, but it may not!
- \end{proof}
-
- \subsection{Canonical amalgamation}
-
- \begin{definition}
- Let $\bK$ be a class finitely generated $L$-structures. We say that
- $\bK$ has \emph{canonical amalgamation} if for every $C\in\bK$ there
- is a functor $\otimes_C\colon\Cospan(\bK)\to\Pushout(\bK)$ such that
- it has the following properties:
- \begin{itemize}
- \item Let $A\leftarrow C\rightarrow B$ be a cospan. Then $\otimes_C$ sends
- it to a pushout that preserves ``the bottom`` structures and embeddings, i.e.:
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- & & & & A\otimes_C B & \\
- A & & B \arrow[r, dashed, "A\otimes_C B"] & A \arrow[ur, dashed] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed] \\
- & C \arrow[ul] \arrow[ur] & & & C \arrow[ul] \arrow[ur] &
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- We have deliberately omited names for embeddings of $C$. Of course,
- the functor has to take them into account, but this abuse of notation
- is convenient and should not lead into confusion.
- \item Let $A\leftarrow C\rightarrow B$, $A'\leftarrow C\rightarrow B'$ be cospans
- with a natural transformation given by $\alpha\colon A\to A', \beta\colon B\to B',
- \gamma\colon C\to C$. Then $\otimes_C$ preserves the morphisms of
- when sending the natural transformation of those cospans to natural
- transformation of pushouts by adding the
- $\delta\colon A\otimes_C B\to A'\otimes_C B'$ morphism:
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- & A'\otimes_C B' & \\
- A' \arrow[ur] & & B' \arrow[ul] \\
- & A\otimes_C B \ar[uu, dashed, "\delta"] & \\
- & C \arrow[uul, bend left] \arrow[uur, bend right] & \\
- A \arrow[uuu, dashed, "\alpha"] \arrow[uur, bend left, crossing over] & & B \arrow[uuu, dashed, "\beta"'] \arrow[uul, bend right, crossing over] \\
- & C \arrow[ur] \arrow[ul] \arrow[uu, dashed, "\gamma"] & \\
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
- % \begin{center}
- % \begin{tikzcd}
- % & A \ar[rrr, dashed, "\alpha"] \ar[drr, bend left=20, crossing over] & & & A' \ar[dr] & \\
- % C \ar[rr, dashed, "\gamma"] \ar[ur] \ar[dr] & & C \ar[rrd, bend right=20] \ar[rru, bend left=20] & A\otimes_C B \ar[rr, dashed, "\delta"] & & A' \otimes_C B' \\
- % & B \ar[rrr, dashed, "\beta"] \ar[urr, bend right=20, crossing over] & & & B' \ar[ur] & \\
- % \end{tikzcd}
- % \end{center}
- \end{itemize}
- \end{definition}
-
- \begin{theorem}
- \label{theorem:canonical_amalgamation_thm}
- Let $\bK$ be a Fraïssé class of $L$-structures with canonical amalgamation.
- Then the class $\cH$ of $L$-structures with automorphism is a Fraïssé class.
- \end{theorem}
-
- \begin{proof}
- $\cH$ is obviously countable and has HP. It suffices to show that it
- has AP (JEP follows by taking $C$ to be the empty structure). Take any
- $(A,\alpha), (B,\beta), (C,\gamma)\in \cH$ such that $(C,\gamma)$ embeds
- into $(A,\alpha)$ and $(B,\beta)$. Then $\alpha, \beta, \gamma$ yield
- an automorphism $\eta$ (as a natural transformation) of a cospan:
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- A & & B \\
- % & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] & \\
- A \ar[u, dashed, "\alpha"] & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] & B \ar[u, dashed, "\beta"'] \\
- & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] \ar[u, dashed, "\gamma"] &
- % (A, \alpha) & & (B, \beta) \\
- % & (C, \gamma) \ar[ur] \ar[ul] &
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- Then, by the fact \ref{fact:functor_iso}, $\otimes_C(\eta)$ is an automorphism
- of the pushout diagram:
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- & A\otimes_C B \ar[loop above, "\delta"] & \\
- A \ar[ur] \ar[loop left, "\alpha"]& & B \ar[ul] \ar[loop right, "\beta"]\\
- & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] \ar[loop below, "\gamma"] &
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- TODO: ten diagram nie jest do końca taki jak trzeba, trzeba w zasadzie skopiować
- ten z definicji kanonicznej amalgamcji. Czy to nie będzie wyglądać źle?
-
- This means that the morphism $\delta\colon A\otimes_C B\to A\otimes_C B$
- has to be automorphism. Thus, by the fact that the diagram commutes,
- we have the amalgamation of $(A, \alpha)$ and $(B, \beta)$ over $(C,\gamma)$
- in $\cH$.
- \end{proof}
-
- \subsection{Graphs with automorphism}
- The language and theory of unordered graphs is fairly simple. We extend the
- language by one unary symbol $\sigma$ and interpret it as an arbitrary
- automorphism on the graph structure. It turns out that the class of such
- structures is a Fraïssé class.
-
- \begin{proposition}
- Let $\cH$ be the class of all finite graphs with an automorphism, i.e.
- structures in the language $(E, \sigma)$ such that $E$ is a symmetric
- relation and $\sigma$ is an automorphism on the structure. $\cH$ is
- a Fraïssé class.
- \end{proposition}
- \begin{proof}
- Countability and HP are obvious, JEP follows by the same argument as in
- plain graphs. We need to show that the class has the amalgamation property.
-
- Take any $(A, \alpha), (B, \beta), (C,\gamma)\in\cH$ such that $A$ embeds
- into $B$ and $C$. Without the loss of generality we may assume that
- $B\cap C = A$ and $\alpha\subseteq\beta,\gamma$.
- Let $D$ be the amalgamation of $B$ and $C$ over $A$ as in
- the proof for the plain graphs. We will define the automorphism
- $\delta\in\Aut(D)$ so it extends $\beta$ and $\gamma$.
- We let $\delta\upharpoonright_B = \beta, \delta\upharpoonright_C = \gamma$.
- Let's check the definition is correct. We have to show that
- $(uE_Dv\leftrightarrow \delta(u)E_D\delta(v))$ holds for any $u, v\in
- D$. We have two cases:
- \begin{itemize}
- \item $u, v\in X$, where $X$ is either $B$ or $C$. This case is trivial.
- \item $u\in B\setminus A, v\in C\setminus A$. Then
- $\delta(u)=\beta(u)\in B\setminus A$, similarly $\delta(v)=\gamma(v)\in
- C\setminus A$. This follows from the fact, that $\beta\upharpoonright_A
- = \alpha$, so for any $w\in A\quad\beta^{-1}(w)=\alpha^{-1}(w)\in A$,
- similarly for $\gamma$. Thus, from the construction of $D$, $\neg uE_Dv$
- and $\neg \delta(u)E_D\delta(v)$.
- \end{itemize}
- \end{proof}
-
- The proposition says that there is a Fraïssé for the class $\cH$ of finite
- graphs with automorphisms. We shall call it $(\FrAut, \sigma)$. Not
- surprisingly, $\FrAut$ is in fact a random graph.
-
- \begin{proposition}
- \label{proposition:graph-aut-is-normal}
- The Fraïssé limit of $\cH$ interpreted as a plain graph (i.e. as a reduct
- to the language of graphs) is isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
- \end{proposition}
-
- \begin{proof}
- It is enough to show that $\FrAut = \Flim(\cH)$ has the random graph
- property. Take any finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq \FrAut$. Without the loss
- of generality assume that $X\cup Y$ is $\sigma$-invariant, i.e.
- $\sigma(v)\in X\cup Y$ for $v\in X\cup Y$. This assumption can be made
- because there are no infinite orbits in $\sigma$, which in turn is due to
- the fact that $\cH$ is the age of $\FrAut$.
-
- Let $G_{XY}$ be the graph induced by $X\cup Y$. Take $H=G_{XY}\sqcup {v}$
- as a supergraph of $G_{XY}$ with one new vertex $v$ connected to all
- vertices of $X$ and to none of $Y$. By the proposition
- \ref{proposition:finite-graphs-whp} we can extend $H$ together with its
- partial isomorphism $\sigma\upharpoonright_{X\cup Y}$ to a graph $R$ with
- automorphism $\tau$. Once again, without the loss of generality we can
- assume that $R\subseteq\FrAut$, because $\cH$ is the age of $\FrAut$. But
- $R\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$ together with $\tau\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$
- are isomorphic to the $G_{XY}$ with $\sigma\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$.
-
- Thus, by ultrahomogeneity of $\FrAut$ this isomorphism extends to an
- automorphism $\theta$ of $(\FrAut, \sigma)$. Then $\theta(v)$ is the vertex
- that is connected to all vertices of $X$ and none of $Y$, because
- $\theta[R\upharpoonright_X] = X, \theta[R\upharpoonright_Y] = Y$.
- \end{proof}
-
-
- \begin{theorem}
- \label{theorem:isomorphic_fr_lims}
- Let $\cC$ be a Fraïssé class of finite structures in a relational language
- $L$ of some theory $T$. Let $\cD$ be a class of finite structures of the
- theory $T$ in a relational language $L$ with additional unary function
- symbol interpreted as an automorphism of the structure. If $\cC$ has the
- weak Hrushovski property and $\cD$ is a Fraïssé class then the Fraïssé
- limit of $\cC$ is isomorphic to the Fraïssé limit of $\cD$ reduced
- to the language $L$.
- \end{theorem}
-
- \begin{proof}
- Let $\Gamma=\Flim(\cC)$ and $(\Pi, \sigma) =\Flim(\cD)$. By the Fraïssé
- theorem \ref{theorem:fraisse_thm} it suffices to show that the age of $\Pi$
- is $\cC$ and that it has the weak ultrahomogeneity in the class $\cC$. The
- former comes easily, as for every structure $A\in \cC$ we have the structure
- $(A, \id_A)\in \cD$, which means that the structure $A$ embedds into $\Pi$.
- Also, if a structure $(B, \beta)\in\cD$ embedds into $\cD$, then $B\in\cC$.
- Hence, $\cC$ is indeed the age of $\Pi$.
-
- Now, take any structure $A, B\in\cC$ such that $A\subseteq B$. Without the
- loss of generality assume that $A = B\cap \Pi$. Let $\bar{A}$ be the
- smallest structure closed on the automorphism $\sigma$ and containg $A$.
- It is finite, as $\cC$ is the age of $\Pi$. By the weak Hrushovski property,
- of $\cC$ let $(\bar{B}, \beta)$ be a structure extending
- $(B\cup \bar{A}, \sigma\upharpoonright_{\bar{A}})$. Again, we may assume
- that $B\cup \bar{A}\subseteq \bar{B}$. Then, by the fact that $\Pi$ is a
- Fraïssé limit of $\cD$ there is an embedding
- $f\colon(\bar{B}, \beta)\to(\Pi, \sigma)$
- such that the following diagram commutes:
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- (A, \emptyset) \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & (\bar{A}, \sigma\upharpoonright_A) \arrow[d, "\subseteq"] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & (\Pi, \sigma) \\
- (B, \sigma\upharpoonright_B) \arrow[r, dashed, "\subseteq"'] & (\bar{B}, \beta) \arrow[ur, dashed, "f"]
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- Then we simply get the following diagram:
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- A \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & \Pi \\
- B \arrow[ur, dashed, "f\upharpoonright_B"']
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- which proves that $\Pi$ is indeed a weakly ultrahomogeneous structure in $\cC$.
- Hence, it is isomorphic to $\Gamma$.
- \end{proof}
+ \subfile{sections/fraisse_classes}
\section{Conjugacy classes in automorphism groups}
+ \subfile{sections/conj_classes}
- Let $M$ be a countable $L$-structure. We define a topology on the $G=\Aut(M)$:
- for any finite function $f\colon M\to M$ we have a basic open set
- $[f]_{G} = \{g\in G\mid f\subseteq g\}$.
-
- \subsection{Prototype: pure set}
-
- In this section, $M=(M,=)$ is an infinite countable set (with no structure
- beyond equality).
-
- \begin{proposition}
- \label{proposition:cojugate-classes}
- If $f_1,f_2\in \Aut(M)$, then $f_1$ and $f_2$ are conjugate if and only
- if for each $n\in \bN\cup \{\aleph_0\}$, $f_1$ and $f_2$ have the same
- number of orbits of size $n$.
- \end{proposition}
-
- \begin{theorem}
- Let $\sigma\in \Aut(M)$ be an automorphism with no infinite orbit and with
- infinitely many orbits of size $n$ for every $n>0$. Then the conjugacy
- class of $\sigma$ is comeagre in $\Aut(M)$.
- \end{theorem}
-
- \begin{proof}
- We will show that the conjugacy class of $\sigma$ is an intersection of countably
- many comeagre sets.
-
- Let $A_n = \{\alpha\in Aut(M)\mid \alpha\text{ has infinitely many orbits of size }n\}$.
- This set is comeagre for every $n>0$. Indeed, we can represent this set
- as an intersection of countable family of open dense sets. Let $B_{n,k}$
- be the set of all finite functions $\beta\colon M\to M$ that consists
- of exactly $k$ distinct $n$-cycles. Then:
- \begin{align*}
- A_n &= \{\alpha\in\ \Aut(M) \mid \alpha\text{ has infinitely many orbits of size }n\} \\
- &= \bigcap_{k=1}^{\infty} \{\alpha\in \Aut(M)\mid \alpha\text{ has at least }k\text{ orbits of size }n\} \\
- &= \bigcap_{k=1}^{\infty} \bigcup_{\beta\in B_{n,k}} [\beta]_{\Aut(M)},
- \end{align*}
- where indeed, $\bigcup_{\beta\in B_{n,k}} [\beta]_{\Aut(M)}$ is dense in
- $\Aut(M)$: take any finite $\gamma\colon M\to M$ such that $[\gamma]_{\Aut(M)}$
- is nonempty. Then also
- $\bigcup_{\beta\in B_{n,k}} [\beta]_{\Aut(M)}\cap[\gamma]_{\Aut(M)}\neq\emptyset$,
- one can easily construct a permutation that extends $\gamma$ and have at least
- $k$ many $n$-cycles.
-
- Now we see that $A = \bigcap_{n=1}^{\infty} A_n$ is a comeagre set consisting
- of all functions that have infinitely many $n$-cycles for each $n$. The only
- thing left to show is that the set of functions with no infinite cycle is
- also comeagre. Indeed, for $m\in M$ let
- $B_m = \{\alpha\in\Aut(M)\mid m\text{ has finite orbit in }\alpha\}$. This
- is an open dense set. It is a sum over basic open sets generated by finite
- permutations with $m$ in their domain. Denseness is also easy to see.
-
- Finally, by the proposition \ref{proposition:cojugate-classes}, we can say that
- $$\sigma^{\Aut(M)}=\bigcap_{n=1}^\infty A_n \cap \bigcap_{m\in M} B_m,$$
- which concludes the proof.
- \end{proof}
-
- \subsection{More general structures}
-
- \begin{fact}
- \label{fact:conjugacy}
- Suppose $M$ is an arbitrary structure and $f_1,f_2\in \Aut(M)$.
- Then $f_1$ and $f_2$ are conjugate if and only if $(M,f_1)\cong
- (M,f_2)$ as structures with one additional unary relation that is
- an automorphism.
- \end{fact}
-
- \begin{proof}
- Suppose that $f_1 = g^{-1}f_2g$ for some $g\in \Aut(M)$.
- Then $g$ is the automorphism we're looking for. On the other hand if
- $g\colon (M, f_1)\to (M, f_2)$ is an isomorphism, then
- $g\circ f_1 = f_2 \circ g$ which exactly means that $f_1, f_2$ conjugate.
- \end{proof}
-
- \begin{theorem}
- \label{theorem:generic_aut_general}
- Let $\cC$ be a Fraïssé class of finite structures of a theory $T$ in a
- relational language $L$. Let $\cD$ be the class of the finite structures of
- $T$ in the language $L$ with additional unary function symbol interpreted
- as an automorphism of the structure. If $\cC$ has the weak Hrushovski property
- and $\cD$ is a Fraïssé class, then there is a comeagre conjugacy class in the
- automorphism group of the $\Flim(\cC)$.
- \end{theorem}
-
- \begin{proof}
- Let $\Gamma = \Flim(\cC)$ and $(\Pi, \sigma) = \Flim(\cD)$. Let $G = \Aut(\Gamma)$,
- i.e. $G$ is the automorphism group of $\Gamma$. First, by the theorem
- \ref{theorem:isomorphic_fr_lims}, we may assume without the loss of generality
- that $\Pi = \Gamma$.
- We will construct a strategy for the second player in the Banach-Mazur game
- on the topological space $G$. This strategy will give us a subset
- $A\subseteq G$ and as we will see a subset of a cojugacy class in $G$.
- By the Banach-Mazur theorem \ref{theorem:banach_mazur_thm} this will prove
- that this class is comeagre.
-
- Recall, $G$ has a basis consisting of open
- sets $\{g\in G\mid g\upharpoonright_A = g_0\upharpoonright_A\}$ for some
- finite set $A\subseteq \Gamma$ and some automorphism $g_0\in G$. In other
- words, a basic open set is a set of all extensions of some finite partial
- isomorphism $g_0$ of $\Gamma$. By $B_{g}\subseteq G$ we denote a basic
- open subset given by a finite partial isomorphism $g$. From now on we will
- consider only finite partial isomorphism $g$ such that $B_g$ is nonempty.
-
- With the use of corollary \ref{corollary:banach-mazur-basis} we can consider
- only games, where both players choose finite partial isomorphisms. Namely,
- player \textit{I} picks functions $f_0, f_1,\ldots$ and player \textit{II}
- chooses $g_0, g_1,\ldots$ such that
- $f_0\subseteq g_0\subseteq f_1\subseteq g_1\subseteq\ldots$, which identify
- the corresponding basic open subsets $B_{f_0}\supseteq B_{g_0}\supseteq\ldots$.
-
- Our goal is to choose $g_i$ in such a manner that the resulting function
- $g = \bigcap^{\infty}_{i=0}g_i$ will be an automorphism of the Fraïssé limit
- $\Gamma$ such that $(\Gamma, g) = \Flim{\cD}$.
- Precisely, $\bigcap^{\infty}_{i=0}B_{g_i} = \{g\}$,
- by the Fraïssé theorem \ref{theorem:fraisse_thm}
- it will follow that $(\Gamma, g)\cong (\Pi, \sigma)$. Hence,
- by the fact \ref{fact:conjugacy}, $g$ and $\sigma$ conjugate in $G$.
-
- Once again, by the Fraïssé theorem \ref{theorem:fraisse_thm} and the
- \ref{lemma:weak_ultrahom} lemma constructing $g_i$'s in a way such that
- age of $(\Gamma, g)$ is exactly $\cD$ and so that it is weakly ultrahomogeneous
- will produce expected result. First, let us enumerate all pairs of structures
- $\{\langle(A_n, \alpha_n), (B_n, \beta_n)\rangle\}_{n\in\bN},\in\cD$
- such that the first element of the pair embeds by inclusion in the second,
- i.e. $(A_n, \alpha_n)\subseteq (B_n, \beta_n)$. Also, it may be that
- $A_n$ is an empty. We enumerate the elements of the Fraïssé limit
- $\Gamma = \{v_0, v_1, \ldots\}$.
-
- Fix a bijection $\gamma\colon\bN\times\bN\to\bN$ such that for any
- $n, m\in\bN$ we have $\gamma(n, m) \ge n$. This bijection naturally induces
- a well ordering on $\bN\times\bN$. This will prove useful later, as the
- main argument of the proof will be constructed as a bookkeeping argument.
-
- Just for sake of fixing a technical problem, let $g_{-1} = \emptyset$ and
- $X_{-1} = \emptyset$.
- Suppose that player \textit{I} in the $n$-th move chooses a finite partial
- isomorphism $f_n$. We will construct $g_n\supseteq f_n$ and a set $X_n\subseteq\bN^2$
- such that following properties hold:
-
- \begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*)]
- \item $g_n$ is an automorphism of the induced substructure $\Gamma_n$,
- \item $g_n(v_n)$ and $g_n^{-1}(v_n)$ are defined,
- \item let
- $\{\langle (A_{n,k}, \alpha_{n, k}), (B_{n,k}, \beta_{n,k}), f_{n, k}\rangle\}_{k\in\bN}$
- be the enumeration of all pairs of finite structures of $T$ with automorphism
- such that the first is a substructure of the second, i.e.
- $(A_{n,k}, \alpha_{n,k})\subseteq (B_{n,k}, \beta_{n,k})$, and $f_{n,k}$
- is an embedding of $(A_{n,k}, \alpha_{n,k})$ in the $\FrGr_{n-1}$ (which
- is the substructure induced by $g_{n-1}$). Let
- $(i, j) = \min\{(\{0, 1, \ldots\} \times \bN) \setminus X_{n-1}\}$ (with the
- order induced by $\gamma$). Then $X_n = X_{n-1}\cup\{(i,j)\}$ and
- $(B_{n,k}, \beta_{n,k})$ embeds in $(\FrGr_n, g_n)$ so that this diagram
- commutes:
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- & (\Gamma_n, g_n) & \\
- (B_{i,j}, \beta_{i,j}) \arrow[ur, dashed, "\hat{f}_{i,j}"] & & (\FrGr_{n-1}, g_{n-1}) \arrow[ul, dashed, "\subseteq"'] \\
- & (A_{i,j}, \alpha_{i,j}) \arrow[ur, "f_{i,j}"'] \arrow[ul, "\subseteq"]
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
- \end{enumerate}
-
- First item makes sure that no infinite orbit will be present in $g$. The
- second item together with the first one are necessary for $g$ to be an
- automorphism of $\Gamma$. The third item is the one that gives weak
- ultrahomogeneity. Now we will show that indeed such $g_n$ may be constructed.
-
- First, we will suffice the item (iii). Namely, we will construct $\Gamma'_n, g'_n$
- such that $g_{n-1}\subseteq g'_n$ and $f_{i,j}$ extends to an embedding of
- $(B_{i,j}, \beta_{i,j})$ to $(\Gamma'_n, g'_n)$. But this can be easily
- done by the fact, that $\cD$ has the amalgamation property. Moreover, without
- the loss of generality we can assume that all embeddings are inclusions.
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- & (\Gamma'_n, g'_n) & \\
- (B_{i,j}, \beta_{i,j}) \arrow[ur, dashed, "\subseteq"] & & (\Gamma_{n-1}, g_{n-1}) \arrow[ul, dashed, "\subseteq"'] \\
- & (A_{i,j}, \alpha_{i,j}) \arrow[ur, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[ul, "\subseteq"]
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- By the weak ultrahomogeneity we may assume that $\Gamma'_n\subseteq \Gamma$:
-
- \begin{center}
- \begin{tikzcd}
- (B_{i,j}\cup\Gamma_{n-1}, \beta_{i,j}\cup g_{n-1}) \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & \Gamma \\
- (\Gamma'_{n}, g'_n)\arrow[ur, dashed, "f"']
- \end{tikzcd}
- \end{center}
-
- Now, by the WHP of $\bK$ we can extend the graph $\Gamma'_n\cup\{v_n\}$ together
- with its partial isomorphism $g'_n$ to a graph $\Gamma_n$ together with its
- automorphism $g_n\supseteq g'_n$ and without the loss of generality we
- may assume that $\Gamma_n\subseteq\Gamma$. This way we've constructed $g_n$
- that has all desired properties.
-
- Now we need to see that $g = \bigcap^{\infty}_{n=0}g_n$ is indeed an automorphism
- of $\Gamma$ such that $(\Gamma, g)$ has the age $\cH$ and is weakly ultrahomogeneous.
- It is of course an automorphism of $\Gamma$ as it is defined for every $v\in\Gamma$
- and is a sum of increasing chain of finite automorphisms.
-
- Take any finite structure of $T$ with automorphism $(B, \beta)$. Then, there are
- $i, j$ such that $(B, \beta) = (B_{i, j}, \beta_{i,j})$ and $A_{i,j}=\emptyset$.
- By the bookkeeping there was $n$ such that
- $(i, j) = \min\{\{0,1,\ldots\}\times\bN\setminus X_{n-1}\}$.
- This means that $(B, \beta)$ embeds into $(\Gamma_n, g_n)$, hence it embeds
- into $(\Gamma, g)$, thus it has age $\cH$.
- With a similar argument we can see that $(\Gamma, g)$ is weakly ultrahomogeneous.
-
- By this we know that $g$ and $\sigma$ conjugate in $G$. As we stated in the
- beginning of the proof, the set $A$ of possible outcomes of the game (i.e.
- possible $g$'s we end up with) is comeagre in $G$, thus $\sigma^G$ is also
- comeagre and $\sigma$ is a generic automorphism, as it contains a comeagre
- set $A$.
- \end{proof}
-
- \subsection{Properties of the generic automorphism}
-
- Let $\cC$ be a Fraïssé class in a finite relational language $L$ with
- weak Hrushovski property. Let $\cH$ be the Fraïssé class of the $L$-structures
- with additional automorphism symbol. Let $\Gamma = \Flim(\cC)$.
-
- % \begin{proposition}
- % Let $\sigma$ be the generic automorphism of the random graph $\FrGr$. Then
- % the graph induced by the set of the fixed points of $\sigma$ is isomorphic
- % to $\FrGr$.
- % \end{proposition}
- %
- % \begin{proof}
- % Let $F = \{v\in\FrGr\mid \sigma(v) = v\}$. It suffices to show that $F$ is
- % infinite and has the random graph property.
- % \end{proof}
- \begin{proposition}
- Let $\sigma$ be the generic automorphism of $\Gamma$. Then the set
- of fixed points of $\sigma$ is isomorphic to $\Gamma$.
- \end{proposition}
-
- \begin{proof}
- Let $S = \{x\in \Gamma\mid \sigma(x) = x\}$.
- First we need to show that it is an infinite. By the theorem \ref{theorem:generic_aut_general}
- we know that $(\Gamma, \sigma)$ is the Fraïssé limit of $\cH$, thus we
- can embedd finite $L$-structures of any size with identity as an
- automorphism of the structure into $(\Gamma, \sigma)$. Thus $S$ has to be
- infinite. Also, the same argument shows that the age of the structure is
- exactly $\cC$. It is weakly ultrahomogeneous, also by the fact that
- $(\Gamma, \sigma)$ is in $\cH$.
- \end{proof}
\printbibliography
\end{document}
diff --git a/sections/conj_classes.tex b/sections/conj_classes.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..8beace0
--- /dev/null
+++ b/sections/conj_classes.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,251 @@
+\documentclass[../lic_malinka.tex]{subfiles}
+
+\begin{document}
+ Let $M$ be a countable $L$-structure. We define a topology on the $G=\Aut(M)$:
+ for any finite function $f\colon M\to M$ we have a basic open set
+ $[f]_{G} = \{g\in G\mid f\subseteq g\}$.
+
+ \subsection{Prototype: pure set}
+
+ In this section, $M=(M,=)$ is an infinite countable set (with no structure
+ beyond equality).
+
+ \begin{proposition}
+ \label{proposition:cojugate-classes}
+ If $f_1,f_2\in \Aut(M)$, then $f_1$ and $f_2$ are conjugate if and only
+ if for each $n\in \bN\cup \{\aleph_0\}$, $f_1$ and $f_2$ have the same
+ number of orbits of size $n$.
+ \end{proposition}
+
+ \begin{theorem}
+ Let $\sigma\in \Aut(M)$ be an automorphism with no infinite orbit and with
+ infinitely many orbits of size $n$ for every $n>0$. Then the conjugacy
+ class of $\sigma$ is comeagre in $\Aut(M)$.
+ \end{theorem}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ We will show that the conjugacy class of $\sigma$ is an intersection of countably
+ many comeagre sets.
+
+ Let $A_n = \{\alpha\in Aut(M)\mid \alpha\text{ has infinitely many orbits of size }n\}$.
+ This set is comeagre for every $n>0$. Indeed, we can represent this set
+ as an intersection of countable family of open dense sets. Let $B_{n,k}$
+ be the set of all finite functions $\beta\colon M\to M$ that consists
+ of exactly $k$ distinct $n$-cycles. Then:
+ \begin{align*}
+ A_n &= \{\alpha\in\ \Aut(M) \mid \alpha\text{ has infinitely many orbits of size }n\} \\
+ &= \bigcap_{k=1}^{\infty} \{\alpha\in \Aut(M)\mid \alpha\text{ has at least }k\text{ orbits of size }n\} \\
+ &= \bigcap_{k=1}^{\infty} \bigcup_{\beta\in B_{n,k}} [\beta]_{\Aut(M)},
+ \end{align*}
+ where indeed, $\bigcup_{\beta\in B_{n,k}} [\beta]_{\Aut(M)}$ is dense in
+ $\Aut(M)$: take any finite $\gamma\colon M\to M$ such that $[\gamma]_{\Aut(M)}$
+ is nonempty. Then also
+ $\bigcup_{\beta\in B_{n,k}} [\beta]_{\Aut(M)}\cap[\gamma]_{\Aut(M)}\neq\emptyset$,
+ one can easily construct a permutation that extends $\gamma$ and have at least
+ $k$ many $n$-cycles.
+
+ Now we see that $A = \bigcap_{n=1}^{\infty} A_n$ is a comeagre set consisting
+ of all functions that have infinitely many $n$-cycles for each $n$. The only
+ thing left to show is that the set of functions with no infinite cycle is
+ also comeagre. Indeed, for $m\in M$ let
+ $B_m = \{\alpha\in\Aut(M)\mid m\text{ has finite orbit in }\alpha\}$. This
+ is an open dense set. It is a sum over basic open sets generated by finite
+ permutations with $m$ in their domain. Denseness is also easy to see.
+
+ Finally, by the proposition \ref{proposition:cojugate-classes}, we can say that
+ $$\sigma^{\Aut(M)}=\bigcap_{n=1}^\infty A_n \cap \bigcap_{m\in M} B_m,$$
+ which concludes the proof.
+ \end{proof}
+
+ \subsection{More general structures}
+
+ \begin{fact}
+ \label{fact:conjugacy}
+ Suppose $M$ is an arbitrary structure and $f_1,f_2\in \Aut(M)$.
+ Then $f_1$ and $f_2$ are conjugate if and only if $(M,f_1)\cong
+ (M,f_2)$ as structures with one additional unary relation that is
+ an automorphism.
+ \end{fact}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ Suppose that $f_1 = g^{-1}f_2g$ for some $g\in \Aut(M)$.
+ Then $g$ is the automorphism we're looking for. On the other hand if
+ $g\colon (M, f_1)\to (M, f_2)$ is an isomorphism, then
+ $g\circ f_1 = f_2 \circ g$ which exactly means that $f_1, f_2$ conjugate.
+ \end{proof}
+
+ \begin{theorem}
+ \label{theorem:generic_aut_general}
+ Let $\cC$ be a Fraïssé class of finite structures of a theory $T$ in a
+ relational language $L$. Let $\cD$ be the class of the finite structures of
+ $T$ in the language $L$ with additional unary function symbol interpreted
+ as an automorphism of the structure. If $\cC$ has the weak Hrushovski property
+ and $\cD$ is a Fraïssé class, then there is a comeagre conjugacy class in the
+ automorphism group of the $\Flim(\cC)$.
+ \end{theorem}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ Let $\Gamma = \Flim(\cC)$ and $(\Pi, \sigma) = \Flim(\cD)$. Let $G = \Aut(\Gamma)$,
+ i.e. $G$ is the automorphism group of $\Gamma$. First, by the theorem
+ \ref{theorem:isomorphic_fr_lims}, we may assume without the loss of generality
+ that $\Pi = \Gamma$.
+ We will construct a strategy for the second player in the Banach-Mazur game
+ on the topological space $G$. This strategy will give us a subset
+ $A\subseteq G$ and as we will see a subset of a cojugacy class in $G$.
+ By the Banach-Mazur theorem \ref{theorem:banach_mazur_thm} this will prove
+ that this class is comeagre.
+
+ Recall, $G$ has a basis consisting of open
+ sets $\{g\in G\mid g\upharpoonright_A = g_0\upharpoonright_A\}$ for some
+ finite set $A\subseteq \Gamma$ and some automorphism $g_0\in G$. In other
+ words, a basic open set is a set of all extensions of some finite partial
+ isomorphism $g_0$ of $\Gamma$. By $B_{g}\subseteq G$ we denote a basic
+ open subset given by a finite partial isomorphism $g$. From now on we will
+ consider only finite partial isomorphism $g$ such that $B_g$ is nonempty.
+
+ With the use of corollary \ref{corollary:banach-mazur-basis} we can consider
+ only games, where both players choose finite partial isomorphisms. Namely,
+ player \textit{I} picks functions $f_0, f_1,\ldots$ and player \textit{II}
+ chooses $g_0, g_1,\ldots$ such that
+ $f_0\subseteq g_0\subseteq f_1\subseteq g_1\subseteq\ldots$, which identify
+ the corresponding basic open subsets $B_{f_0}\supseteq B_{g_0}\supseteq\ldots$.
+
+ Our goal is to choose $g_i$ in such a manner that the resulting function
+ $g = \bigcap^{\infty}_{i=0}g_i$ will be an automorphism of the Fraïssé limit
+ $\Gamma$ such that $(\Gamma, g) = \Flim{\cD}$.
+ Precisely, $\bigcap^{\infty}_{i=0}B_{g_i} = \{g\}$,
+ by the Fraïssé theorem \ref{theorem:fraisse_thm}
+ it will follow that $(\Gamma, g)\cong (\Pi, \sigma)$. Hence,
+ by the fact \ref{fact:conjugacy}, $g$ and $\sigma$ conjugate in $G$.
+
+ Once again, by the Fraïssé theorem \ref{theorem:fraisse_thm} and the
+ \ref{lemma:weak_ultrahom} lemma constructing $g_i$'s in a way such that
+ age of $(\Gamma, g)$ is exactly $\cD$ and so that it is weakly ultrahomogeneous
+ will produce expected result. First, let us enumerate all pairs of structures
+ $\{\langle(A_n, \alpha_n), (B_n, \beta_n)\rangle\}_{n\in\bN},\in\cD$
+ such that the first element of the pair embeds by inclusion in the second,
+ i.e. $(A_n, \alpha_n)\subseteq (B_n, \beta_n)$. Also, it may be that
+ $A_n$ is an empty. We enumerate the elements of the Fraïssé limit
+ $\Gamma = \{v_0, v_1, \ldots\}$.
+
+ Fix a bijection $\gamma\colon\bN\times\bN\to\bN$ such that for any
+ $n, m\in\bN$ we have $\gamma(n, m) \ge n$. This bijection naturally induces
+ a well ordering on $\bN\times\bN$. This will prove useful later, as the
+ main argument of the proof will be constructed as a bookkeeping argument.
+
+ Just for sake of fixing a technical problem, let $g_{-1} = \emptyset$ and
+ $X_{-1} = \emptyset$.
+ Suppose that player \textit{I} in the $n$-th move chooses a finite partial
+ isomorphism $f_n$. We will construct $g_n\supseteq f_n$ and a set $X_n\subseteq\bN^2$
+ such that following properties hold:
+
+ \begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*)]
+ \item $g_n$ is an automorphism of the induced substructure $\Gamma_n$,
+ \item $g_n(v_n)$ and $g_n^{-1}(v_n)$ are defined,
+ \item let
+ $\{\langle (A_{n,k}, \alpha_{n, k}), (B_{n,k}, \beta_{n,k}), f_{n, k}\rangle\}_{k\in\bN}$
+ be the enumeration of all pairs of finite structures of $T$ with automorphism
+ such that the first is a substructure of the second, i.e.
+ $(A_{n,k}, \alpha_{n,k})\subseteq (B_{n,k}, \beta_{n,k})$, and $f_{n,k}$
+ is an embedding of $(A_{n,k}, \alpha_{n,k})$ in the $\FrGr_{n-1}$ (which
+ is the substructure induced by $g_{n-1}$). Let
+ $(i, j) = \min\{(\{0, 1, \ldots\} \times \bN) \setminus X_{n-1}\}$ (with the
+ order induced by $\gamma$). Then $X_n = X_{n-1}\cup\{(i,j)\}$ and
+ $(B_{n,k}, \beta_{n,k})$ embeds in $(\FrGr_n, g_n)$ so that this diagram
+ commutes:
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ & (\Gamma_n, g_n) & \\
+ (B_{i,j}, \beta_{i,j}) \arrow[ur, dashed, "\hat{f}_{i,j}"] & & (\FrGr_{n-1}, g_{n-1}) \arrow[ul, dashed, "\subseteq"'] \\
+ & (A_{i,j}, \alpha_{i,j}) \arrow[ur, "f_{i,j}"'] \arrow[ul, "\subseteq"]
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+ \end{enumerate}
+
+ First item makes sure that no infinite orbit will be present in $g$. The
+ second item together with the first one are necessary for $g$ to be an
+ automorphism of $\Gamma$. The third item is the one that gives weak
+ ultrahomogeneity. Now we will show that indeed such $g_n$ may be constructed.
+
+ First, we will suffice the item (iii). Namely, we will construct $\Gamma'_n, g'_n$
+ such that $g_{n-1}\subseteq g'_n$ and $f_{i,j}$ extends to an embedding of
+ $(B_{i,j}, \beta_{i,j})$ to $(\Gamma'_n, g'_n)$. But this can be easily
+ done by the fact, that $\cD$ has the amalgamation property. Moreover, without
+ the loss of generality we can assume that all embeddings are inclusions.
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ & (\Gamma'_n, g'_n) & \\
+ (B_{i,j}, \beta_{i,j}) \arrow[ur, dashed, "\subseteq"] & & (\Gamma_{n-1}, g_{n-1}) \arrow[ul, dashed, "\subseteq"'] \\
+ & (A_{i,j}, \alpha_{i,j}) \arrow[ur, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[ul, "\subseteq"]
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ By the weak ultrahomogeneity we may assume that $\Gamma'_n\subseteq \Gamma$:
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ (B_{i,j}\cup\Gamma_{n-1}, \beta_{i,j}\cup g_{n-1}) \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & \Gamma \\
+ (\Gamma'_{n}, g'_n)\arrow[ur, dashed, "f"']
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ Now, by the WHP of $\bK$ we can extend the graph $\Gamma'_n\cup\{v_n\}$ together
+ with its partial isomorphism $g'_n$ to a graph $\Gamma_n$ together with its
+ automorphism $g_n\supseteq g'_n$ and without the loss of generality we
+ may assume that $\Gamma_n\subseteq\Gamma$. This way we've constructed $g_n$
+ that has all desired properties.
+
+ Now we need to see that $g = \bigcap^{\infty}_{n=0}g_n$ is indeed an automorphism
+ of $\Gamma$ such that $(\Gamma, g)$ has the age $\cH$ and is weakly ultrahomogeneous.
+ It is of course an automorphism of $\Gamma$ as it is defined for every $v\in\Gamma$
+ and is a sum of increasing chain of finite automorphisms.
+
+ Take any finite structure of $T$ with automorphism $(B, \beta)$. Then, there are
+ $i, j$ such that $(B, \beta) = (B_{i, j}, \beta_{i,j})$ and $A_{i,j}=\emptyset$.
+ By the bookkeeping there was $n$ such that
+ $(i, j) = \min\{\{0,1,\ldots\}\times\bN\setminus X_{n-1}\}$.
+ This means that $(B, \beta)$ embeds into $(\Gamma_n, g_n)$, hence it embeds
+ into $(\Gamma, g)$, thus it has age $\cH$.
+ With a similar argument we can see that $(\Gamma, g)$ is weakly ultrahomogeneous.
+
+ By this we know that $g$ and $\sigma$ conjugate in $G$. As we stated in the
+ beginning of the proof, the set $A$ of possible outcomes of the game (i.e.
+ possible $g$'s we end up with) is comeagre in $G$, thus $\sigma^G$ is also
+ comeagre and $\sigma$ is a generic automorphism, as it contains a comeagre
+ set $A$.
+ \end{proof}
+
+ \subsection{Properties of the generic automorphism}
+
+ Let $\cC$ be a Fraïssé class in a finite relational language $L$ with
+ weak Hrushovski property. Let $\cH$ be the Fraïssé class of the $L$-structures
+ with additional automorphism symbol. Let $\Gamma = \Flim(\cC)$.
+
+ % \begin{proposition}
+ % Let $\sigma$ be the generic automorphism of the random graph $\FrGr$. Then
+ % the graph induced by the set of the fixed points of $\sigma$ is isomorphic
+ % to $\FrGr$.
+ % \end{proposition}
+ %
+ % \begin{proof}
+ % Let $F = \{v\in\FrGr\mid \sigma(v) = v\}$. It suffices to show that $F$ is
+ % infinite and has the random graph property.
+ % \end{proof}
+ \begin{proposition}
+ Let $\sigma$ be the generic automorphism of $\Gamma$. Then the set
+ of fixed points of $\sigma$ is isomorphic to $\Gamma$.
+ \end{proposition}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ Let $S = \{x\in \Gamma\mid \sigma(x) = x\}$.
+ First we need to show that it is an infinite. By the theorem \ref{theorem:generic_aut_general}
+ we know that $(\Gamma, \sigma)$ is the Fraïssé limit of $\cH$, thus we
+ can embedd finite $L$-structures of any size with identity as an
+ automorphism of the structure into $(\Gamma, \sigma)$. Thus $S$ has to be
+ infinite. Also, the same argument shows that the age of the structure is
+ exactly $\cC$. It is weakly ultrahomogeneous, also by the fact that
+ $(\Gamma, \sigma)$ is in $\cH$.
+ \end{proof}
+\end{document}
diff --git a/sections/fraisse_classes.tex b/sections/fraisse_classes.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..ca2247e
--- /dev/null
+++ b/sections/fraisse_classes.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,451 @@
+\documentclass[../lic_malinka.tex]{subfiles}
+
+\begin{document}
+ In this section we will take a closer look at classes of finitely
+ generated structures with some characteristic properties. More
+ specifically, we will describe a concept developed by a French
+ mathematician Roland Fraïssé called Fraïssé limit.
+
+ \subsection{Definitions}
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $L$ be a signature and $M$ be an $L$-structure. The \emph{age} of $M$ is
+ the class $\bK$ of all finitely generated structures that embeds into $M$.
+ The age of $M$ is also associated with class of all structures embeddable in
+ $M$ \emph{up to isomorphism}.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ We say that $M$ has \emph{countable age} when its age has countably many
+ isomorphism types of finitely generated structures.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated structures. $\bK$ has
+ \emph{hereditary property (HP)} if for any $A\in\bK$, any finitely generated
+ substructure $B$ of $A$ it holds that $B\in\bK$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated structures. We say that $\bK$ has
+ \emph{joint embedding property (JEP)} if for any $A, B\in\bK$ there is a
+ structure $C\in\bK$ such that both $A$ and $B$ embed in $C$.
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ & C & \\
+ A \arrow[ur, dashed, "f"] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed, "g"']
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ In terms of category theory, this is a \emph{span} in category $\bK$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ Fraïssé has shown fundamental theories regarding age of a structure, one of
+ them being the following one:
+
+ \begin{fact}
+ \label{fact:age_is_hpjep}
+ Suppose $L$ is a signature and $\bK$ is a nonempty finite or countable set
+ of finitely generated $L$-structures. Then $\bK$ has the HP and JEP if
+ and only if $\bK$ is the age of some finite or countable structure.
+ \end{fact}
+
+ Beside the HP and JEP Fraïssé has distinguished one more property of the
+ class $\bK$, namely amalgamation property.
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $\bK$ be a class of finitely generated $L$-structures. We say that $\bK$
+ has the \emph{amalgamation property (AP)} if for any $A, B, C\in\bK$ and
+ embeddings $e\colon C\to A, f\colon C\to B$ there exists $D\in\bK$ together
+ with embeddings $g\colon A\to D$ and $h\colon A\to D$ such that
+ $g\circ e = h\circ f$.
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ & D & \\
+ A \arrow[ur, dashed, "g"] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed, "h"'] \\
+ & C \arrow[ur, "f"'] \arrow[ul, "e"]
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+ \end{definition}
+
+ In terms of category theory, amalgamation over some structure $C$ is a
+ pushout diagram.
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $M$ be an $L$-structure. $M$ is \emph{ultrahomogeneous} if every
+ isomorphism between finitely generated substructures of $M$ extends to an
+ automorphism of $M$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ Having those definitions we can provide the main Fraïssé theorem.
+
+ \begin{theorem}[Fraïssé theorem]
+ \label{theorem:fraisse_thm}
+ Let L be a countable language and let $\bK$ be a nonempty countable set of
+ finitely generated $L$-structures which has HP, JEP and AP. Then $\bK$ is
+ the age of a countable, ultrahomogeneous $L$-structure $M$. Moreover, $M$ is
+ unique up to isomorphism. We say that $M$ is a \emph{Fraïssé limit} of $\bK$
+ and denote this by $M = \Flim(\bK)$.
+ \end{theorem}
+
+ This is a well known theorem. One can read a proof of this theorem in Wilfrid
+ Hodges' classical book \textit{Model Theory}~\cite{hodges_1993}. In the proof
+ of this theorem appears another, equally important \ref{lemma:weak_ultrahom}.
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ We say that an $L$-structure $M$ is \emph{weakly ultrahomogeneous} if for any
+ $A, B$ finitely generated substructures of $M$ such that $A\subseteq B$ and
+ an embedding $f\colon A\to M$ there is an embedding $g\colon B\to M$ which
+ extends $f$.
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ A \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "f"] & D \\
+ B \arrow[ur, dashed, "g"']
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{lemma}
+ \label{lemma:weak_ultrahom}
+ A countable structure is ultrahomogeneous if and only if it is weakly
+ ultrahomogeneous.
+ \end{lemma}
+
+ This lemma will play a major role in the later parts of the paper. Weak
+ ultrahomogeneity is an easier and more intuitive property and it will prove
+ useful when recursively constructing the generic automorphism of a Fraïssé
+ limit.
+
+ % \begin{fact} If $\bK$ is a uniformly locally finite Fraïssé class, then
+ % $\Flim(\bK)$ is $\aleph_0$-categorical and has quantifier elimination.
+ % \end{fact}
+
+ \subsection{Random graph}
+
+ In this section we'll take a closer look on a class of finite unordered graphs,
+ which is a Fraïssé class.
+
+ The language of unordered graphs $L$ consists of a single binary
+ relational symbol $E$. If $G$ is an $L$-structure then we call it a
+ \emph{graph}, and its elements $\emph{vertices}$. If for some vertices
+ $u, v\in G$ we have $G\models uEv$ then we say that there is an $\emph{edge}$
+ connecting $u$ and $v$. If $G\models \forall x\forall y (xEy\leftrightarrow yEx)$
+ then we say that $G$ is an \emph{unordered graph}. From now on we omit the word
+ \textit{unordered} and graphs as unordered.
+
+ \begin{proposition}
+ Let $\cG$ be the class of all finite graphs. $\cG$ is a Fraïssé class.
+ \end{proposition}
+ \begin{proof}
+ $\cG$ is of course countable (up to isomorphism) and has the HP
+ (graph substructure is also a graph). It has JEP: having two finite graphs
+ $G_1,G_2$ take their disjoint union $G_1\sqcup G_2$ as the extension of them
+ both. $\cG$ has the AP. Having graphs $A, B, C$, where $B$ and $C$ are
+ supergraphs of $A$, we can assume without loss of generality, that
+ $(B\setminus A) \cap (C\setminus A) = \emptyset$. Then
+ $A\sqcup (B\setminus A)\sqcup (C\setminus A)$ is the graph we're looking
+ for (with edges as in B and C and without any edges between $B\setminus A$
+ and $C\setminus A$).
+ \end{proof}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ The \emph{random graph} is the Fraïssé limit of the class of finite graphs
+ $\cG$ denoted by $\FrGr = \Flim(\cG)$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ The concept of the random graph emerges independently in many fields of
+ mathematics. For example, one can construct the graph by choosing at random
+ for each pair of vertices if they should be connected or not. It turns out
+ that the graph constructed this way is isomorphic to the random graph with
+ probability 1.
+
+ The random graph $\FrGr$ has one particular property that is unique to the
+ random graph.
+
+ \begin{fact}[random graph property]
+ For each finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq \FrGr$ there exists $v\in\FrGr\setminus (X\cup Y)$
+ such that $\forall u\in X (vEu)$ and $\forall u\in Y (\neg vEu)$.
+ \end{fact}
+ \begin{proof}
+ Take any finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq\FrGr$. Let $G_{XY}$ be the
+ subgraph of $\FrGr$ induced by the $X\cup Y$. Let $H = G_{XY}\cup \{w\}$,
+ where $w$ is a new vertex that does not appear in $G_{XY}$. Also, $w$ is connected to
+ all vertices of $G_{XY}$ that come from $X$ and to none of those that come
+ from $Y$. This graph is of course finite, so it is embeddable in $\FrGr$.
+ Without loss of generality assume that this embedding is simply inclusion.
+ Let $f$ be the partial isomorphism from $X\sqcup Y$ to $H$, with $X$ and
+ $Y$ projected to the part of $H$ that come from $X$ and $Y$ respectively.
+ By the ultrahomogeneity of $\FrGr$ this isomorphism extends to an automorphism
+ $\sigma\in\Aut(\FrGr)$. Then $v = \sigma^{-1}(w)$ is the vertex we sought.
+ \end{proof}
+
+ \begin{fact}
+ If a countable graph $G$ has the random graph property, then it is
+ isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
+ \end{fact}
+ \begin{proof}
+ Enumerate vertices of both graphs: $\FrGr = \{a_1, a_2\ldots\}$ and $G
+ = \{b_1, b_2\ldots\}$.
+ We will construct a chain of partial isomorphisms $f_n\colon \FrGr\to G$
+ such that $\emptyset = f_0\subseteq f_1\subseteq f_2\subseteq\ldots$ and $a_n \in
+ \dom(f_n)$ and $b_n\in\rng(f_n)$.
+
+ Suppose we have $f_n$. We seek $b\in G$ such that $f_n\cup \{\langle
+ a_{n+1}, b\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism.
+ If $a_{n+1}\in\dom{f_n}$, then simply $b = f_n(a_{n+1})$. Otherwise,
+ let $X = \{a\in\FrGr\mid
+ aE_{\FrGr} a_{n+1}\}\cap \dom{f_n}, Y = X^{c}\cap \dom{f_n}$, i.e. $X$ are
+ vertices of $\dom{f_n}$ that are connected with $a_{n+1}$ in $\FrGr$ and
+ $Y$ are those vertices that are not connected with $a_{n+1}$. Let $b$ be
+ a vertex of $G$ that is connected to all vertices of $f_n[X]$ and to none
+ $f_n[Y]$ (it exists by the random graph property). Then $f_n\cup \{\langle
+ a_{n+1}, b\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism. We find $a$ for the
+ $b_{n+1}$ in the similar manner, so that $f_{n+1} = f_n\cup \{\langle
+ a_{n+1}, b\rangle, \langle a, b_{n+1}\rangle\}$ is a partial isomorphism.
+
+ Finally, $f = \bigcup^{\infty}_{n=0}f_n$ is an isomorphism between $\FrGr$
+ and $G$. Take any $a, b\in \FrGr$. Then for some big enough $n$ we have
+ that $aE_{\FrGr}b\Leftrightarrow f_n(a)E_{G}f_n(b) \Leftrightarrow f(a)E_{G}f(b)$.
+ \end{proof}
+
+ Using this fact one can show that the graph constructed in the probabilistic
+ manner is in fact isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
+
+ \begin{definition} We say that a Fraïssé class $\bK$ has \emph{weak
+ Hrushovski property} (\emph{WHP}) if for every $A\in \bK$ and an isomorphism
+ of its substructures $p\colon A\to A$ (also called a partial automorphism of $A$),
+ there is some $B\in \bK$ such
+ that $p$ can be extended to an automorphism of $B$, i.e.\ there is an
+ embedding $i\colon A\to B$ and a $\bar p\in \Aut(B)$ such that the following
+ diagram commutes:
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ B\ar[r,dashed,"\bar p"]&B\\
+ A\ar[u,dashed,"i"]\ar[r,"p"]&A\ar[u,dashed,"i"]
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{proposition}
+ \label{proposition:finite-graphs-whp}
+ The class of finite graphs $\cG$ has the weak Hrushovski property.
+ \end{proposition}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ It may be there some day, but it may not!
+ \end{proof}
+
+ \subsection{Canonical amalgamation}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $\bK$ be a class finitely generated $L$-structures. We say that
+ $\bK$ has \emph{canonical amalgamation} if for every $C\in\bK$ there
+ is a functor $\otimes_C\colon\Cospan(\bK)\to\Pushout(\bK)$ such that
+ it has the following properties:
+ \begin{itemize}
+ \item Let $A\leftarrow C\rightarrow B$ be a cospan. Then $\otimes_C$ sends
+ it to a pushout that preserves ``the bottom`` structures and embeddings, i.e.:
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ & & & & A\otimes_C B & \\
+ A & & B \arrow[r, dashed, "A\otimes_C B"] & A \arrow[ur, dashed] & & B \arrow[ul, dashed] \\
+ & C \arrow[ul] \arrow[ur] & & & C \arrow[ul] \arrow[ur] &
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ We have deliberately omited names for embeddings of $C$. Of course,
+ the functor has to take them into account, but this abuse of notation
+ is convenient and should not lead into confusion.
+ \item Let $A\leftarrow C\rightarrow B$, $A'\leftarrow C\rightarrow B'$ be cospans
+ with a natural transformation given by $\alpha\colon A\to A', \beta\colon B\to B',
+ \gamma\colon C\to C$. Then $\otimes_C$ preserves the morphisms of
+ when sending the natural transformation of those cospans to natural
+ transformation of pushouts by adding the
+ $\delta\colon A\otimes_C B\to A'\otimes_C B'$ morphism:
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ & A'\otimes_C B' & \\
+ A' \arrow[ur] & & B' \arrow[ul] \\
+ & A\otimes_C B \ar[uu, dashed, "\delta"] & \\
+ & C \arrow[uul, bend left] \arrow[uur, bend right] & \\
+ A \arrow[uuu, dashed, "\alpha"] \arrow[uur, bend left, crossing over] & & B \arrow[uuu, dashed, "\beta"'] \arrow[uul, bend right, crossing over] \\
+ & C \arrow[ur] \arrow[ul] \arrow[uu, dashed, "\gamma"] & \\
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+ % \begin{center}
+ % \begin{tikzcd}
+ % & A \ar[rrr, dashed, "\alpha"] \ar[drr, bend left=20, crossing over] & & & A' \ar[dr] & \\
+ % C \ar[rr, dashed, "\gamma"] \ar[ur] \ar[dr] & & C \ar[rrd, bend right=20] \ar[rru, bend left=20] & A\otimes_C B \ar[rr, dashed, "\delta"] & & A' \otimes_C B' \\
+ % & B \ar[rrr, dashed, "\beta"] \ar[urr, bend right=20, crossing over] & & & B' \ar[ur] & \\
+ % \end{tikzcd}
+ % \end{center}
+ \end{itemize}
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{theorem}
+ \label{theorem:canonical_amalgamation_thm}
+ Let $\bK$ be a Fraïssé class of $L$-structures with canonical amalgamation.
+ Then the class $\cH$ of $L$-structures with automorphism is a Fraïssé class.
+ \end{theorem}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ $\cH$ is obviously countable and has HP. It suffices to show that it
+ has AP (JEP follows by taking $C$ to be the empty structure). Take any
+ $(A,\alpha), (B,\beta), (C,\gamma)\in \cH$ such that $(C,\gamma)$ embeds
+ into $(A,\alpha)$ and $(B,\beta)$. Then $\alpha, \beta, \gamma$ yield
+ an automorphism $\eta$ (as a natural transformation) of a cospan:
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ A & & B \\
+ % & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] & \\
+ A \ar[u, dashed, "\alpha"] & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] & B \ar[u, dashed, "\beta"'] \\
+ & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] \ar[u, dashed, "\gamma"] &
+ % (A, \alpha) & & (B, \beta) \\
+ % & (C, \gamma) \ar[ur] \ar[ul] &
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ Then, by the fact \ref{fact:functor_iso}, $\otimes_C(\eta)$ is an automorphism
+ of the pushout diagram:
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ & A\otimes_C B \ar[loop above, "\delta"] & \\
+ A \ar[ur] \ar[loop left, "\alpha"]& & B \ar[ul] \ar[loop right, "\beta"]\\
+ & C \ar[ur] \ar[ul] \ar[loop below, "\gamma"] &
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ TODO: ten diagram nie jest do końca taki jak trzeba, trzeba w zasadzie skopiować
+ ten z definicji kanonicznej amalgamcji. Czy to nie będzie wyglądać źle?
+
+ This means that the morphism $\delta\colon A\otimes_C B\to A\otimes_C B$
+ has to be automorphism. Thus, by the fact that the diagram commutes,
+ we have the amalgamation of $(A, \alpha)$ and $(B, \beta)$ over $(C,\gamma)$
+ in $\cH$.
+ \end{proof}
+
+ \subsection{Graphs with automorphism}
+ The language and theory of unordered graphs is fairly simple. We extend the
+ language by one unary symbol $\sigma$ and interpret it as an arbitrary
+ automorphism on the graph structure. It turns out that the class of such
+ structures is a Fraïssé class.
+
+ \begin{proposition}
+ Let $\cH$ be the class of all finite graphs with an automorphism, i.e.
+ structures in the language $(E, \sigma)$ such that $E$ is a symmetric
+ relation and $\sigma$ is an automorphism on the structure. $\cH$ is
+ a Fraïssé class.
+ \end{proposition}
+ \begin{proof}
+ Countability and HP are obvious, JEP follows by the same argument as in
+ plain graphs. We need to show that the class has the amalgamation property.
+
+ Take any $(A, \alpha), (B, \beta), (C,\gamma)\in\cH$ such that $A$ embeds
+ into $B$ and $C$. Without the loss of generality we may assume that
+ $B\cap C = A$ and $\alpha\subseteq\beta,\gamma$.
+ Let $D$ be the amalgamation of $B$ and $C$ over $A$ as in
+ the proof for the plain graphs. We will define the automorphism
+ $\delta\in\Aut(D)$ so it extends $\beta$ and $\gamma$.
+ We let $\delta\upharpoonright_B = \beta, \delta\upharpoonright_C = \gamma$.
+ Let's check the definition is correct. We have to show that
+ $(uE_Dv\leftrightarrow \delta(u)E_D\delta(v))$ holds for any $u, v\in
+ D$. We have two cases:
+ \begin{itemize}
+ \item $u, v\in X$, where $X$ is either $B$ or $C$. This case is trivial.
+ \item $u\in B\setminus A, v\in C\setminus A$. Then
+ $\delta(u)=\beta(u)\in B\setminus A$, similarly $\delta(v)=\gamma(v)\in
+ C\setminus A$. This follows from the fact, that $\beta\upharpoonright_A
+ = \alpha$, so for any $w\in A\quad\beta^{-1}(w)=\alpha^{-1}(w)\in A$,
+ similarly for $\gamma$. Thus, from the construction of $D$, $\neg uE_Dv$
+ and $\neg \delta(u)E_D\delta(v)$.
+ \end{itemize}
+ \end{proof}
+
+ The proposition says that there is a Fraïssé for the class $\cH$ of finite
+ graphs with automorphisms. We shall call it $(\FrAut, \sigma)$. Not
+ surprisingly, $\FrAut$ is in fact a random graph.
+
+ \begin{proposition}
+ \label{proposition:graph-aut-is-normal}
+ The Fraïssé limit of $\cH$ interpreted as a plain graph (i.e. as a reduct
+ to the language of graphs) is isomorphic to the random graph $\FrGr$.
+ \end{proposition}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ It is enough to show that $\FrAut = \Flim(\cH)$ has the random graph
+ property. Take any finite disjoint $X, Y\subseteq \FrAut$. Without the loss
+ of generality assume that $X\cup Y$ is $\sigma$-invariant, i.e.
+ $\sigma(v)\in X\cup Y$ for $v\in X\cup Y$. This assumption can be made
+ because there are no infinite orbits in $\sigma$, which in turn is due to
+ the fact that $\cH$ is the age of $\FrAut$.
+
+ Let $G_{XY}$ be the graph induced by $X\cup Y$. Take $H=G_{XY}\sqcup {v}$
+ as a supergraph of $G_{XY}$ with one new vertex $v$ connected to all
+ vertices of $X$ and to none of $Y$. By the proposition
+ \ref{proposition:finite-graphs-whp} we can extend $H$ together with its
+ partial isomorphism $\sigma\upharpoonright_{X\cup Y}$ to a graph $R$ with
+ automorphism $\tau$. Once again, without the loss of generality we can
+ assume that $R\subseteq\FrAut$, because $\cH$ is the age of $\FrAut$. But
+ $R\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$ together with $\tau\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$
+ are isomorphic to the $G_{XY}$ with $\sigma\upharpoonright_{G_{XY}}$.
+
+ Thus, by ultrahomogeneity of $\FrAut$ this isomorphism extends to an
+ automorphism $\theta$ of $(\FrAut, \sigma)$. Then $\theta(v)$ is the vertex
+ that is connected to all vertices of $X$ and none of $Y$, because
+ $\theta[R\upharpoonright_X] = X, \theta[R\upharpoonright_Y] = Y$.
+ \end{proof}
+
+
+ \begin{theorem}
+ \label{theorem:isomorphic_fr_lims}
+ Let $\cC$ be a Fraïssé class of finite structures in a relational language
+ $L$ of some theory $T$. Let $\cD$ be a class of finite structures of the
+ theory $T$ in a relational language $L$ with additional unary function
+ symbol interpreted as an automorphism of the structure. If $\cC$ has the
+ weak Hrushovski property and $\cD$ is a Fraïssé class then the Fraïssé
+ limit of $\cC$ is isomorphic to the Fraïssé limit of $\cD$ reduced
+ to the language $L$.
+ \end{theorem}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ Let $\Gamma=\Flim(\cC)$ and $(\Pi, \sigma) =\Flim(\cD)$. By the Fraïssé
+ theorem \ref{theorem:fraisse_thm} it suffices to show that the age of $\Pi$
+ is $\cC$ and that it has the weak ultrahomogeneity in the class $\cC$. The
+ former comes easily, as for every structure $A\in \cC$ we have the structure
+ $(A, \id_A)\in \cD$, which means that the structure $A$ embedds into $\Pi$.
+ Also, if a structure $(B, \beta)\in\cD$ embedds into $\cD$, then $B\in\cC$.
+ Hence, $\cC$ is indeed the age of $\Pi$.
+
+ Now, take any structure $A, B\in\cC$ such that $A\subseteq B$. Without the
+ loss of generality assume that $A = B\cap \Pi$. Let $\bar{A}$ be the
+ smallest structure closed on the automorphism $\sigma$ and containg $A$.
+ It is finite, as $\cC$ is the age of $\Pi$. By the weak Hrushovski property,
+ of $\cC$ let $(\bar{B}, \beta)$ be a structure extending
+ $(B\cup \bar{A}, \sigma\upharpoonright_{\bar{A}})$. Again, we may assume
+ that $B\cup \bar{A}\subseteq \bar{B}$. Then, by the fact that $\Pi$ is a
+ Fraïssé limit of $\cD$ there is an embedding
+ $f\colon(\bar{B}, \beta)\to(\Pi, \sigma)$
+ such that the following diagram commutes:
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ (A, \emptyset) \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & (\bar{A}, \sigma\upharpoonright_A) \arrow[d, "\subseteq"] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & (\Pi, \sigma) \\
+ (B, \sigma\upharpoonright_B) \arrow[r, dashed, "\subseteq"'] & (\bar{B}, \beta) \arrow[ur, dashed, "f"]
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ Then we simply get the following diagram:
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ A \arrow[d, "\subseteq"'] \arrow[r, "\subseteq"] & \Pi \\
+ B \arrow[ur, dashed, "f\upharpoonright_B"']
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ which proves that $\Pi$ is indeed a weakly ultrahomogeneous structure in $\cC$.
+ Hence, it is isomorphic to $\Gamma$.
+ \end{proof}
+\end{document}
diff --git a/sections/introduction.tex b/sections/introduction.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..89004c7
--- /dev/null
+++ b/sections/introduction.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,5 @@
+\documentclass[../lic_malinka.tex]{subfiles}
+
+\begin{document}
+ There will be something!
+\end{document}
diff --git a/sections/preliminaries.tex b/sections/preliminaries.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..832beae
--- /dev/null
+++ b/sections/preliminaries.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,347 @@
+\documentclass[../lic_malinka.tex]{subfiles}
+
+\begin{document}
+ \subsection{Descriptive set theory}
+ \begin{definition}
+ Suppose $X$ is a topological space and $A\subseteq X$.
+ We say that $A$ is \emph{meagre} in $X$ if $A = \bigcup_{n\in\bN}A_n$,
+ where $A_n$ are nowhere dense subsets of $X$ (i.e. $\Int(\bar{A_n})
+ = \emptyset$).
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ We say that $A$ is \emph{comeagre} in $X$ if it is
+ a complement of a meagre set. Equivalently, a set is comeagre if and only if it
+ contains a countable intersection of open dense sets.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ % \begin{example}
+ Every countable set is meagre in any $T_1$ space, so, for example, $\bQ$
+ is meagre in $\bR$ (although it is dense), which means that the set of
+ irrationals is comeagre. Another example is...
+ % \end{example}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ We say that a topological space $X$ is a \emph{Baire space} if every
+ comeagre subset of $X$ is dense in $X$ (equivalently, every meagre set has
+ empty interior).
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Suppose $X$ is a Baire space. We say that a property $P$ \emph{holds
+ generically} for a point $x\in X$ if $\{x\in X\mid P\textrm{ holds for
+ }x\}$ is comeagre in $X$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $X$ be a nonempty topological space and let
+ $A\subseteq X$. The \emph{Banach-Mazur game of $A$}, denoted as
+ $G^{\star\star}(A)$ is defined as follows: Players $I$ and
+ $\textit{II}$ take turns in playing nonempty open sets $U_0, V_0,
+ U_1, V_1,\ldots$ such that $U_0 \supseteq V_0 \supseteq U_1 \supseteq
+ V_1 \supseteq\ldots$. We say that player $\textit{II}$ wins the game if
+ $\bigcap_{n}V_n \subseteq A$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ There is an important theorem on the Banach-Mazur game: $A$ is comeagre
+ if and only if $\textit{II}$ can always choose sets $V_0, V_1, \ldots$ such that
+ it wins. Before we prove it we need to define notions necessary to
+ formalise and prove the theorem.
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ $T$ is \emph{the tree of all legal positions} in the Banach-Mazur game
+ $G^{\star\star}(A)$ when $T$ consists of all finite sequences $(W_0,
+ W_1,\ldots, W_n)$, where $W_i$ are nonempty open sets such that
+ $W_0\supseteq W_1\supseteq\ldots\supseteq W_n$. In other words, $T$ is
+ a pruned tree on $\{W\subseteq X\mid W \textrm{is open nonempty}\}$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ We say that $\sigma$ is \emph{a pruned subtree} of the tree of all legal
+ positions $T$ if $\sigma\subseteq T$, for any $(W_0, W_1, \ldots,
+ W_n)\in\sigma, n\ge 0$ there is a $W$ such that $(W_0, W_1,\ldots, W_n,
+ W)\in\sigma$ (it simply means that there's no finite branch in~$\sigma$) and
+ $(W_0, W_1,\ldots W_{n-1})\in\sigma$ (every node on a branch is in $\sigma$).
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $\sigma$ be a pruned subtree of the tree of all legal positions $T$. By
+ $[\sigma]$ we denote \emph{the set of all infinite branches of $\sigma$},
+ i.e. infinite sequences $(W_0, W_1, \ldots)$ such that $(W_0, W_1, \ldots
+ W_n)\in \sigma$ for any $n\in \bN$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ A \emph{strategy} for $\textit{II}$ in
+ $G^{\star\star}(A)$ is a pruned subtree $\sigma\subseteq T$ such that
+ \begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*)]
+ \item $\sigma$ is nonempty,
+ \item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n, V_n)\in\sigma$, then for all open
+ nonempty $U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$, $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n, V_n,
+ U_{n+1})\in\sigma$,
+ \item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{n})\in\sigma$, then for a unique $V_n$,
+ $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{n}, V_n)\in\sigma$.
+ \end{enumerate}
+ \end{definition}
+
+ Intuitively, a strategy $\sigma$ works as follows: $I$ starts playing
+ $U_0$ as any open subset of $X$, then $\textit{II}$ plays unique (by
+ (iii)) $V_0$ such that $(U_0, V_0)\in\sigma$. Then $I$ responds by
+ playing any $U_1\subseteq V_0$ and $\textit{II}$ plays unique $V_1$
+ such that $(U_0, V_0, U_1, V_1)\in\sigma$, etc.
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ A strategy $\sigma$ is a \emph{winning strategy for $\textit{II}$} if for
+ any game $(U_0, V_0\ldots)\in [\sigma]$ player $\textit{II}$ wins, i.e.
+ $\bigcap_{n}V_n \subseteq A$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ Now we can state the key theorem.
+
+ \begin{theorem}[Banach-Mazur, Oxtoby]
+ \label{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}
+ Let $X$ be a nonempty topological space and let $A\subseteq X$. Then A is
+ comeagre $\Leftrightarrow$ $\textit{II}$ has a winning strategy in
+ $G^{\star\star}(A)$.
+ \end{theorem}
+
+ In order to prove it we add an auxiliary definition and lemma.
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $S\subseteq\sigma$ be a pruned subtree of tree of all legal positions
+ $T$ and let $p=(U_0, V_0,\ldots, V_n)\in S$. We say that S is
+ \emph{comprehensive for p} if the family $\cV_p = \{V_{n+1}\mid (U_0,
+ V_0,\ldots, V_n, U_{n+1}, V_{n+1})\in S\}$ (it may be that $n=-1$, which
+ means $p=\emptyset$) is pairwise disjoint and $\bigcup\cV_p$ is dense in
+ $V_n$ (where we think that $V_{-1} = X$).
+ We say that $S$ is \emph{comprehensive} if it is comprehensive for
+ each $p=(U_0, V_0,\ldots, V_n)\in S$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{fact}
+ If $\sigma$ is a winning strategy for $\mathit{II}$ then
+ there exists a nonempty comprehensive $S\subseteq\sigma$.
+ \end{fact}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ We construct $S$ recursively as follows:
+ \begin{enumerate}
+ \item $\emptyset\in S$,
+ \item if $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n)\in S$, then $(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_n,
+ V_n)\in S$ for the unique $V_n$ given by the strategy $\sigma$,
+ \item let $p = (U_0, V_0, \ldots, V_n)\in S$. For a possible player $I$'s
+ move $U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ let $U^\star_{n+1}$ be the unique set
+ player $\mathit{II}$ would respond with by $\sigma$. Now, by Zorn's
+ Lemma, let $\cU_p$ be a maximal collection of nonempty open subsets
+ $U_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ such that the set $\{U^\star_{n+1}\mid
+ U_{n+1}\in\cU_p\}$ is pairwise disjoint. Then put in $S$ all $(U_0,
+ V_0, \ldots, V_{n}, U_{n+1})$ such that $U_{n+1} \in \cU_p$. This way
+ $S$ is comprehensive for $p$: the family $\cV_p = \{V_{n+1}\mid (U_0,
+ V_0,\ldots, V_n, U_{n+1}, V_{n+1})\in S\}$ is exactly
+ $\{U^\star_{n+1}\mid U_{n+1}\in\cU_p\}$, which is pairwise disjoint and
+ $\bigcup\cV_p$ is obviously dense in $V_n$ by the maximality of $\cU_p$
+ -- if there was any open set $\tilde{U}_{n+1}\subseteq V_n$ disjoint
+ from $\bigcup\cV_p$, then $\tilde{U}^{\star}_{n+1}\subseteq
+ \tilde{U}_{n+1}$ would be also disjoint from $\bigcup\cV_p$, so the
+ family $\cU_p\cup\{\tilde{U}_{n+1}\}$ would violate the maximality of
+ $\cU_p$.
+ \qedhere
+ \end{enumerate}
+ \end{proof}
+
+ \begin{lemma}
+ \label{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}
+ Let $S$ be a nonempty comprehensive pruned subtree of a strategy $\sigma$.
+ Then:
+ \begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*)]
+ \item For any open $V_n\subseteq X$ there is at most one $p=(U_0, V_0,
+ \ldots, U_n, V_n)\in S$.
+ \item Let $S_n = \{V_n\mid (U_0, V_0, \ldots, V_n)\in S\}$ for $n\in\bN$
+ (i.e. $S_n$ is a family of all possible choices player $\textit{II}$
+ can make in its $n$-th move according to $S$). Then $\bigcup S_n$ is
+ open and dense in $X$.
+ \item $S_n$ is a family of pairwise disjoint sets.
+ \end{enumerate}
+ \end{lemma}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ (i): Suppose that there are some $p = (U_0, V_0,\ldots,
+ U_n, V_n)$, $p'=(U'_0, V'_0, \ldots, U'_n, V'_n)$ such that $V_n
+ = V'_n$ and $p \neq p'$. Let $k$ be the smallest index such that those
+ sequences differ. We have two possibilities:
+ \begin{itemize}
+ \item $U_k = U'_k$ and $V_k\neq V'_k$ -- this cannot be true simply by
+ the fact that $S$ is a subset of a strategy (so $V_k$ is unique for
+ $U_k$). \item $U_k\neq U'_k$: by the comprehensiveness of $S$ we know
+ that for $q =(U_0, V_0, \ldots, U_{k-1}, V_{k-1})$ the set $\cV_q$ is
+ pairwise disjoint. Thus $V_k\cap V'_k=\emptyset$, because $V_k, V'_k\in
+ \cV_q$. But this leads to a contradiction -- $V_n$ cannot be a nonempty
+ subset of both $V_k, V'_k$.
+ \end{itemize}
+
+ (ii): The lemma is proved by induction on $n$. For $n=0$ it follows
+ trivially from the definition of comprehensiveness. Now suppose the
+ lemma is true for $n$. Then the set $\bigcup_{V_n\in
+ S_n}\bigcup\cV_{p_{V_n}}$ (where $p_{V_n}$ is given uniquely from
+ (i)) is dense and open in $X$ by the induction hypothesis. But
+ $\bigcup S_{n+1}$ is exactly this set, thus it is dense and open in
+ $X$.
+
+ (iii): We will prove it by induction on $n$. Once again, the case $n
+ = 0$ follows from the comprehensiveness of $S$. Now suppose that the
+ sets in $S_n$ are pairwise disjoint. Take some $x \in V_{n+1}\in
+ S_{n+1}$. Of course $\bigcup S_n \supseteq \bigcup S_{n+1}$, thus by
+ the inductive hypothesis $x\in V_{n}$ for the unique $V_n\in S_n$. It
+ must be that $V_{n+1}\in \cV_{p_{V_n}}$, because $V_n$ is the only
+ superset of $V_{n+1}$ in $S_n$. But $\cV_{p_{V_n}}$ is disjoint, so
+ there is no other $V'_{n+1}\in \cV_{p_{V_n}}$ such that $x\in
+ V'_{n+1}$. Moreover, there is no such set in
+ $S_{n+1}\setminus\cV_{p_{V_n}}$, because those sets are disjoint from
+ $V_{n}$. Hence there is no $V'_{n+1}\in S_{n+1}$ other than $V_n$
+ such that $x\in V'_{n+1}$. We've chosen $x$ and $V_{n+1}$ arbitrarily,
+ so $S_{n+1}$ is pairwise disjoint.
+ \end{proof}
+
+ Now we can move to the proof of the Banach-Mazur theorem.
+
+ \begin{proof}[Proof of theorem \ref{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}]
+ $\Rightarrow$: Let $(A_n)$ be a sequence of dense open sets with
+ $\bigcap_n A_n\subseteq A$. The simply $\textit{II}$ plays $V_n
+ = U_n\cap A_n$, which is nonempty by the denseness of $A_n$.
+
+ $\Leftarrow$: Suppose $\textit{II}$ has a winning strategy $\sigma$.
+ We will show that $A$ is comeagre. Take a comprehensive $S\subseteq
+ \sigma$. We claim that $\mathcal{S} = \bigcap_n\bigcup S_n \subseteq
+ A$. By the lemma~\ref{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}, (ii) sets $\bigcup
+ S_n$ are open and dense, thus $A$ must be comeagre. Now we prove the
+ claim towards contradiction.
+
+ Suppose there is $x\in \mathcal{S}\setminus A$. By the lemma
+ \ref{lemma:comprehensive_lemma}, (iii) for any $n$ there is unique
+ $x\in V_n\in S_n$. It follows that $p_{V_0}\subset
+ p_{V_1}\subset\ldots$. Now the game $(U_0, V_0, U_1, V_1,\ldots)
+ = \bigcup_n p_{V_n}\in [S]\subseteq [\sigma]$ is not winning for
+ player $\textit{II}$, which contradicts the assumption that $\sigma$ is
+ a winning strategy. \end{proof}
+
+ \begin{corollary}
+ \label{corollary:banach-mazur-basis}
+ If we add a constraint to the Banach-Mazur game such that players can only
+ choose basic open sets, then the theorem \ref{theorem:banach_mazur_thm}
+ still suffices.
+ \end{corollary}
+
+ \begin{proof}
+ If one adds the word \textit{basic} before each occurrence
+ of word \textit{open} in previous proofs and theorems then they all
+ will still be valid (except for $\Rightarrow$, but its an easy fix --
+ take $V_n$ a basic open subset of $U_n\cap A_n$).
+ \end{proof}
+
+ This corollary will be important in using the theorem in practice --
+ it's much easier to work with basic open sets rather than any open
+ sets.
+
+ \subsection{Category theory}
+
+ In this section we will give a short introduction to the notions of
+ category theory that will be necessary to generalize the key result of the
+ paper.
+
+ We will use a standard notation. If the reader is interested in detailed
+ introduction to the category theory, then it's recommended to take a look
+ at \cite{maclane_1978}. Here we will shortly describe the standard notation.
+
+ A \emph{category} $\cC$ consists of the collection of objects (denoted as
+ $\Obj(\cC)$, but most often simply as $\cC$) and collection of \emph{morphisms}
+ $\Mor(A, B)$ between each pair of objects $A, B\in \cC$. We require that
+ for each morphisms $f\colon B\to C$, $g\colon A\to B$ there is a morphism
+ $f\circ g\colon A\to C$. For every $A\in\cC$ there is an
+ \emph{identity morphism} $\id_A$ such that for any morphism $f\in \Mor(A, B)$
+ it follows that $f\circ id_A = \id_B \circ f$.
+
+ We say that $f\colon A\to B$ is \emph{isomorphism} if there is (necessarily
+ unique) morphism $g\colon B\to A$ such that $g\circ f = id_A$ and $f\circ g = id_B$.
+ Automorphism is an isomorphism where $A = B$.
+
+ A \emph{functor} is a ``homeomorphism`` of categories. We say that
+ $F\colon\cC\to\cD$ is a functor
+ from category $\cC$ to category $\cD$ if it associates each object $A\in\cC$
+ with an object $F(A)\in\cD$, associates each morphism $f\colon A\to B$ in
+ $\cC$ with a morphism $F(f)\colon F(A)\to F(B)$. We also require that
+ $F(\id_A) = \id_{F(A)}$ and that for any (compatible) morphisms $f, g$ in $\cC$
+ $F(f\circ g) = F(f) \circ F(g)$.
+
+ In category theory we distinguish \emph{covariant} and \emph{contravariant}
+ functors. Here, we only consider \emph{covariant functors}, so we will simply
+ say \emph{functor}.
+
+ \begin{fact}
+ \label{fact:functor_iso}
+ Functor $F\colon\cC\to\cD$ maps isomorphism $f\colon A\to B$ in $\cC$
+ to the isomorphism $F(f)\colon F(A)\to F(B)$ in $\cD$.
+ \end{fact}
+
+ Notion that will be very important for us is a ``morphism of functors``
+ which is called \emph{natural transformation}.
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $F, G$ be functors between the categories $\cC, \cD$. A \emph{natural
+ transformation}
+ $\tau$ is function that assigns to each object $A$ of $\cC$ a morphism $\tau_A$
+ in $\Mor(F(A), G(A))$ such that for every morphism $f\colon A\to B$ in $\cC$
+ the following diagram commutes:
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ A \arrow[d, "f"] & F(A) \arrow[r, "\tau_A"] \arrow[d, "F(f)"] & G(A) \arrow[d, "G(f)"] \\
+ B & F(B) \arrow[r, "\tau_B"] & G(B) \\
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ In category theory, a \emph{diagram} of type $\mathcal{J}$ in category $\cC$
+ is a functor $D\colon \mathcal{J}\to\cC$. $\mathcal{J}$ is called the
+ \emph{index category} of $D$. In other words, $D$ is of \emph{shape} $\mathcal{J}$.
+
+ For example, $\mathcal{J} = \{-1\leftarrow 0 \rightarrow 1\}$, then a diagram
+ $D\colon\mathcal{J}\to \cC$ is called a \emph{cospan}. For example,
+ if $A, B, C$ are objects of $\cC$ and $f\in\Mor(C, A), g\in\Mor(C, B)$, then
+ the following diagram is a cospan:
+
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ A & & B \\
+ & C \arrow[ur, "g"'] \arrow[ul, "f"] &
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+ \end{definition}
+
+ From now we omit explicit definition of the index category, as it is easily
+ referable from a picture.
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ Let $A, B, C, D$ be objects in the category $\cC$ with morphisms
+ $e\colon C\to A, f\colon C\to B, g\colon A\to D, h\colon B\to D$ such
+ that $g\circ e = h\circ f$.
+ Then the following diagram:
+ \begin{center}
+ \begin{tikzcd}
+ & D & \\
+ A \arrow[ur, "g"] & & B \arrow[ul, "h"'] \\
+ & C \arrow[ur, "e"'] \arrow[ul, "f"] &
+ \end{tikzcd}
+ \end{center}
+
+ is called a \emph{pushout} diagram
+ \end{definition}
+
+ \begin{definition}
+ The \emph{cospan category} of category $\cC$, refered to as $\Cospan(\cC)$,
+ is the category of cospan diagrams of $\cC$, where morphisms between
+ two cospans are normal transformations of the underlying functors.
+
+ We define \emph{pushout category} analogously and call it $\Pushout(\cC)$.
+ \end{definition}
+
+ TODO: dodać tu przykład?
+\end{document}